Статті в журналах з теми "Self (Philosophy)"

Щоб переглянути інші типи публікацій з цієї теми, перейдіть за посиланням: Self (Philosophy).

Оформте джерело за APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard та іншими стилями

Оберіть тип джерела:

Ознайомтеся з топ-50 статей у журналах для дослідження на тему "Self (Philosophy)".

Біля кожної праці в переліку літератури доступна кнопка «Додати до бібліографії». Скористайтеся нею – і ми автоматично оформимо бібліографічне посилання на обрану працю в потрібному вам стилі цитування: APA, MLA, «Гарвард», «Чикаго», «Ванкувер» тощо.

Також ви можете завантажити повний текст наукової публікації у форматі «.pdf» та прочитати онлайн анотацію до роботи, якщо відповідні параметри наявні в метаданих.

Переглядайте статті в журналах для різних дисциплін та оформлюйте правильно вашу бібліографію.

1

Joo, Kwang-Sun. "Intercultural Philosophy and Self-theologizing." Journal of the Daedong Philosophical Association 94 (March 31, 2021): 393–421. http://dx.doi.org/10.20539/deadong.2021.94.016.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
2

Lee, Taesoo. "Philosophy as Self-examination and Korean Philosophy." Journal of Philosophical Research 37, no. 9999 (2012): 353–60. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/jpr201237supplement53.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
3

Bowen, Amber. "Reviving the Dead: A Kierkegaardian Turn from the Self-Positing to the Theological Self." Religions 10, no. 11 (November 15, 2019): 633. http://dx.doi.org/10.3390/rel10110633.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
Kierkegaard scholars have traditionally chosen to read Kierkegaard as either a theologian or a philosopher. As a result, his corpus is bifurcated as theologians and philosophers lean on their preferred texts. Beneath this practice is an underlying assumption that philosophy and theology “make two,” or should be kept in separate corners. However, a contemporary movement in philosophy known as New Phenomenology has challenged this dualistic maxim and instead finds it appropriate for phenomenology to draw from a theological archive. This article suggests that the possibilities New Phenomenology makes available help us retroactively better understand Kierkegaard’s text, Sickness unto Death. Fictional author, Anti-Climacus uses theology strategically to open up J. G. Fichte’s ontological monism and to move constructively beyond the dead end of his philosophy. Sickness unto Death effectively demonstrates New Phenomenologist, Emmanuel Falque’s claim that the more we theologize, the better we philosophize.
4

Mungwini, Pascah. "Philosophy, Openness, and the imperative of continuous self-renewal." Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions 11, no. 2 (September 23, 2022): 27–42. http://dx.doi.org/10.4314/ft.v11i2.3.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
Philosophy premises itself on the ideals of openness and continuous self-renewal. And yet, the story of philosophy has been an endless struggle against the violence of systematic exclusion and erasure. This article deploys the principle of openness as an analytic category to reflect on the broader question of epistemic decolonisation and the imperative this imposes on the practice of philosophy. There are important ontological, epistemological, and ethical dimensions to the principle of openness with a bearing on the enterprise and how to conceptualise its future. Whether at the global level or within a specific individual tradition, the principle of openness is about the reconfiguration of philosophy itself and restoring its richness and diversity. For the African philosopher, this entails assuming responsibility for the ongoing task of articulating ‘what philosophy is and what it can be’ within the context of Africa’s own history, its problematics, and priority questions.
5

Welsh. "Philosophy as Self-Transformation:." Journal of Speculative Philosophy 28, no. 4 (2014): 489. http://dx.doi.org/10.5325/jspecphil.28.4.0489.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
6

Bolotnikova, Elena N. "Philosophy as Self-Care." Dialogue and Universalism 24, no. 3 (2014): 50–56. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/du201424357.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
7

Polka, Brayton. "Self-Referentiality and Philosophy." European Legacy 19, no. 7 (October 2, 2014): 906–9. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10848770.2014.965527.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
8

Laitinen, Arto. "Philosophy and self-expression." Philosophy & Social Criticism 44, no. 7 (August 20, 2018): 764–66. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0191453718781244.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
9

Tauber, Alfred I. "Philosophy as Self-Knowledge." Philosophia 42, no. 1 (August 11, 2013): 1–23. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11406-013-9474-x.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
10

Peña‐Guzmán, David M., and Rebekah Spera. "The Philosophical Personality." Hypatia 32, no. 4 (2017): 911–27. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/hypa.12355.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
The authors adopt a critico‐sociological methodology to investigate the current state of the philosophical profession. According to them, the question concerning the status of philosophy (“What is philosophy?”) cannot be answered from within the precinct of philosophical reason alone, since philosophy—understood primarily as a profession—is marked by a constitutive type of self‐ignorance that prevents it from reflecting upon its own sociological conditions of actuality. This ignorance, which is both cause and effect of the organization and investment of philosophical desire, causes philosophers to lose themselves in an ideological myth (“the philosopher as idea(l)”) according to which philosophers are unaffected by the material conditions in which they exist. This myth prevents philosophers from noticing the extent to which their activity is influenced by extra‐philosophical determinants that shape, empirically, who becomes a professional philosopher (“the philosopher as imago”) and who doesn't. This article explores the relationship between philosophy's “idea(l)” and its “imago” as a way of shedding light on some of the mechanisms that make philosophy inhospitable for so many women, people of color, and economic minorities.
11

Gavrilov, Mikhail. "Topicality of philosophic practice for self-determination of modern philosophy." Socium i vlast, no. 1 (2018): 88–93. http://dx.doi.org/10.22394/1996-0522-2018-1-88-93.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
12

Hanson, Karen. "Dressing Down Dressing Up—The Philosophic Fear of Fashion." Hypatia 5, no. 2 (1990): 107–21. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-2001.1990.tb00420.x.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
There is, to all appearances, a philosophic hostility to fashionable dress. Studying this contempt, this paper examines likely sources in philosophy's suspicion of change; anxiety about surfaces and the inessential; failures in the face of death; and the philosophic disdain for, denial of, the human body and human passivity. If there are feminist concerns about fashion, they should be radically different from those of traditional philosophy. Whatever our ineluctable worries about desire and death, whatever our appropriate anger and impatience with the merely superficial, whatever our genuine need to mark off the serious from the trivial, feminism may be a corrective therapy for philosophy's bad humor and self-deception, as these manifest themselves when the subject turns to beautiful clothes.
13

Crisp, Roger. "Sidgwick and Self-interest." Utilitas 2, no. 2 (November 1990): 267–80. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0953820800000698.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
The notion of self-interest has not received from philosophers of this century the attention it deserves. In this paper, I shall first elucidate the views on self-interest of a philosopher who nourished in the last century. It could be argued that Henry Sidgwick's views on this topic are the most considered in the history of philosophy. I shall then point to a number of misconceptions in his position, and suggest a more satisfactory account. I shall attempt also to solve a problem for this new account with the aid of a Sidgwickian distinction.
14

Matsyna, Andrey I. "“Natural Work” as Self-capability." Dialogue and Universalism 30, no. 1 (2020): 105–17. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/du20203017.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
A great wandering humanist philosopher, enlightener and outstanding poet Grigory Savvich Skovoroda’s work pertains to a difficult period in the life of the 18th century Eastern Ukraine. Against the background of growing injustice and evil, the decline of spiritual values, an authentic practical philosophy of individual opposition to a self-serving world steeped in vice was born. Skovoroda’s philosophy completely lacks the intention to consider proprietary interests as the driving force of human development. Its key principle of human development is self-examination within one’s own energy-activity-object-related space. The call for self-examination from the perspective of the authentic idea of “natural work” is revealed dynamically as the process of bringing the objective world into harmony with the nature of an individual. “Natural work” is a process of individual’s constant creative self-overcoming on the ascent to subject identity; total communion of man with the universal whole.
15

Daujotytė-Pakerienė, Viktorija. "Between Philosophy and Self-Reflection." Literatūra 62, no. 1 (December 28, 2020): 24–33. http://dx.doi.org/10.15388/litera.2020.1.2.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
The article aims at highlighting the uniqueness of thinking and academic activity of Donatas Sauka, who for many years was a professor at the Department of Lithuanian Literature of Vilnius University. The article reveals his scholarly ambitions – broad interests, good knowledge of classic Western literature, and an attempt to keep the achievements of natural sciences on the horizon of humanities. However, he harboured artistic and poetic inclinations in his nature; he has translated a number of classical texts required for his research. The philological interests of the professor were permeated by self-reflection. Comparative literature science was his field of research – even though his other interests also competed for his attention, he analysed methodological issues, different scopes of national literatures and paradoxes of literary analysis. He also raised an essential question for comparison – from what and how are clusters of literary identity formed; how they are related to the mental history and language of a nation; how creative incentives are formed and how they operate.
16

Flage, Daniel E. "Hume’s Philosophy of the Self." International Philosophical Quarterly 44, no. 2 (2004): 276–78. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/ipq200444217.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
17

Breazeale, Daniel. "Philosophy and the Divided Self." Fichte-Studien 6 (1994): 117–47. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/fichte199469.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
18

Daujotytė-Pakerienė, Viktorija. "Between Philosophy and Self-Reflection." Literatūra 62, no. 1 (December 28, 2020): 24–33. http://dx.doi.org/10.15388/litera.2020.1.2.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
The article aims at highlighting the uniqueness of thinking and academic activity of Donatas Sauka, who for many years was a professor at the Department of Lithuanian Literature of Vilnius University. The article reveals his scholarly ambitions – broad interests, good knowledge of classic Western literature, and an attempt to keep the achievements of natural sciences on the horizon of humanities. However, he harboured artistic and poetic inclinations in his nature; he has translated a number of classical texts required for his research. The philological interests of the professor were permeated by self-reflection. Comparative literature science was his field of research – even though his other interests also competed for his attention, he analysed methodological issues, different scopes of national literatures and paradoxes of literary analysis. He also raised an essential question for comparison – from what and how are clusters of literary identity formed; how they are related to the mental history and language of a nation; how creative incentives are formed and how they operate.
19

van Ackeren, Marcel, and Alfred Archer. "Self-Sacrifice and Moral Philosophy." International Journal of Philosophical Studies 26, no. 3 (May 27, 2018): 301–7. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09672559.2018.1489638.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
20

Degenhardt, M. A. B. "Should Philosophy Express the Self?" Journal of Philosophy of Education 37, no. 1 (February 2003): 35–51. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/1467-9752.3701003.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
21

Hansen, Jennifer, and Jeffrey Maynes. "Psychiatry, philosophy and the self." Current Opinion in Psychiatry 18, no. 6 (November 2005): 649–52. http://dx.doi.org/10.1097/01.yco.0000184415.44329.11.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
22

Stepin, Vyacheslav S. "Philosophy as Cultural Self-Awareness." Russian Studies in Philosophy 53, no. 2 (April 3, 2015): 151–58. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/10611967.2015.1096699.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
23

BRENDEL, Elke. "SELF-REFERENTIAL ARGUMENTS IN PHILOSOPHY." Grazer Philosophische Studien 74, no. 1 (2007): 177–97. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/9789401204651_010.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
24

Yu, Jiyuan. "Soul and Self: Comparing Chinese Philosophy and Greek Philosophy." Philosophy Compass 3, no. 4 (July 2008): 604–18. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-9991.2008.00152.x.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
25

Nemtsev, Mikhail. "On Professional Self-Determination of Philosophy Teachers in Russia." Ideas and Ideals 13, no. 1-1 (March 19, 2021): 24–41. http://dx.doi.org/10.17212/2075-0862-2021-13.1.1-24-41.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
In the beginning of this paper, the author presents a critical analysis of “The Carnival Time: Russian High School and Science in the Postmodern Era” by P. A. Orekhovsky and V. I. Razumov who scrutinize ongoing degradation in Russian science and education. This crisis is a local variation of deep global crisis (described among others by B. Readings (1996)). Their article represents such a particular feature of humanities in Russian higher educational institutions, as systematic lack of attention to personal educational interests of students that unavoidably leads to certain monologicity. Before now, there has been gnoseological inequality between teachers and students. Thereby, objectives and content of education were predetermined. Global crisis of education is grounded by factual disappearance of this inequality. However, one can appreciate new possibilities for philosophy teachers to live on according to their professional self-determination. In the second part of the article, it is proposed to evaluate the situation from the standpoint of dedicated philosophers for whom teaching is the most appropriate way to fulfill their professional self-determination. Philosophy is a unique profession, where it is barely impossible to separate professional thinking of a philosopher from the practice of teaching Philosophy. To teach philosophy is to philosophize. In this paper, the author considers the term ‘self-determination’ as creation of general value grounds of the philosophy teachers’ practical (everyday) activity, which provides every professional activity with justification as reasonably necessary to establish these values. Self-determination establishes a bridge between personal ethics and everyday practical life decisions. In order to implement their self-determination, philosophers need educational situations. Therefore the main proposition of this paper is that philosophy teachers have a chance to take advantage of the ongoing situation if they develop self-determination and explore educational interests of prospective students.
26

Fořtová, Hana. "Být člověkem a být filosofem podle J.-J. Rousseaua." REFLEXE 2021, no. 60 (September 16, 2021): 97–119. http://dx.doi.org/10.14712/25337637.2021.19.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
The present paper aims to analyse how Rousseau conceives the possibility of being a philosopher and how he views the task of philosophy. While Rousseau is very critical towards contemporary philosophers and philosophy in general, he does describe his own enquiry as a philosophical one. In his view, the proper task of philosophy is ‘the knowledge of man’ that can be also understood as ‘the knowledge of oneself’. As Rousseau states in the Second Discourse, such knowledge is to be accomplished through our reason, yet the philosophy of his time fails in this task because the philosophers let themselves be dominated by their opinions. This claim is related to Rousseau’s distinction between love of oneself (amour de soi) and self-love (amour-propre). While reason is present in men naturally, it develops only under necessity related to the progress of society and social passions. Therefore, it cannot serve as the criterion of rightful conduct; this task belongs to conscience. As has been shown by Derathé, only man truly listening to his conscience can use his reason properly. Rather than to direct one’s self-love in a right direction, it seems that the solution of the problem for a philosopher is to convert self-love back to love of one-self to recreate the original unity of his person. Being human and being a philosopher thus becomes the same thing and the turn towards oneself can become the foundation of true self-understanding as well as true relationship to others.
27

Hentrup, Miles. "Self-Completing Skepticism." Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 23, no. 1 (2018): 105–23. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/epoche2018725122.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
In his 1802 article for the Critical Journal of Philosophy, “Relationship of Skepticism to Philosophy,” Hegel attempts to articulate a form of skepticism that is “at one with every true philosophy.” Focusing on the priority that Hegel gives to ancient skepticism over its modern counterpart, Michael Forster and other commentators suggest that it is Pyrrhonism that Hegel views as one with philosophy. Since Hegel calls attention to the persistence of dogmatism even in the work of Sextus Empiricus, however, I argue that it is only a sublated form of Pyrrhonism, what in the Phenomenology of Spirit he calls “self-completing skepticism,” that Hegel takes to be part of genuine philosophical cognition. In this way, I hope to show that the insight that motivates Hegel’s engagement with skepticism in the 1802 essay comes to inform the philosophical itinerary of the Phenomenology of Spirit.
28

Howes, Moira. "The Self of Philosophy and the Self of Immunology." Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 42, no. 1 (1998): 118–30. http://dx.doi.org/10.1353/pbm.1998.0046.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
29

Velleman, J. David. "Self to Self." Philosophical Review 105, no. 1 (January 1996): 39. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2185763.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
30

ARGY, ANNE-GAËLLE. "On the Uses and Abuses of Nietzsche in Self-Help Literature." PhaenEx 11, no. 2 (December 1, 2016): 49–69. http://dx.doi.org/10.22329/p.v11i2.4781.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
This paper investigates the uses that self-help literature makes of Nietzsche’s philosophy. Some specific concepts of his philosophy, as well as his choices in terms of expression, made Nietzsche a topmost reference for self-help authors in the U.S. and in France. As a philosopher and a nearly legendary figure, Nietzsche, in a strange way, fits more easily than other philosophers in the self-help project of leading people, through practical advices, to peace and happiness. Through examples taken from American and French self-help literature, and with comparisons made with other philosophers, this paper shows how self-help functions when it comes to borrowing from other people’s works.
31

Ogura, Michiko. "Him self him selfe,andhim selfa: A reflexive pronoun + uninflected or nominativeself∗." Studia Neophilologica 60, no. 2 (January 1988): 149–57. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00393278808587995.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
32

Azhimov, Felix E. "International Congress of Philosophy as a Self-Consciousness of Philosophy." Voprosy Filosofii, no. 12 (2020): 16–19. http://dx.doi.org/10.21146/0042-8744-2020-12-16-19.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
The author suggests rethinking the institutional status of philosophy in the con­text of the analysis of International philosophical congresses as collective forms of expression of thought. It is stated that communication platforms for philo­sophical debates such as seminars, conferences, congresses, etc. largely deter­mine the content of philosophical knowledge, therefore it is impossible to raise the question of “pure” philosophy, free from the sphere of conversation (Tatiana G. Shchedrina), in which philosophy is produced as an event. Science and phi­losophy as communicative phenomena require collective forms of work. Scien­tific communities are an indispensable attribute of the existence of science, just like philosophy is the presence of a philosophical school, college, lyceum, acad­emy. Even if science and philosophy are done “armchairly”, then the “armchair” format also presupposes a communication platform, a network of communica­tion between different authors. In this sense, any conferences, congresses, and round tables – with a successful coincidence of academic circumstances – be­come not just a continuation of philosophy but also a direct part. On them, not only and not so much the “philosophical result” is presented, but the process of philosophizing is going on. This indisputable significance of World congresses as collective forms of philosophy and as its self-consciousness was recorded by the famous Russian logician N.A. Vasiliev when he was thinking about the re­sults of the Third World Congress of Philosophy.
33

McDonald, Christie. "Sarah Kofman: Effecting Self Translation." TTR : traduction, terminologie, rédaction 11, no. 2 (February 27, 2007): 185–97. http://dx.doi.org/10.7202/037340ar.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
Abstract Sarah Kofman : Effecting Self Translation — In Sarah Kofman's work, philosophical and psychoanalytical analysis modulate into "life writing" and create a kind of translation which neither alone can fully explain. For Kofman, translation in this sense goes back to readings in philosophy, psychoanalysis and linguistics in order to effect change. Reading Nietzsche through Freud, and Freud through Nietzsche, Sarah Kofman unleashes powerful analytical tools from which emerge a very personal kind of writing in Rue Ordener, rue Labat. What is at stake is the destiny of woman, the extraordinary story of this woman-writer-philosopher and the relationship between life and thought.
34

Tulchinskii, G. L. "The philosophy of the text as texts of philosophy." Slovo.ru: Baltic accent 10, no. 4 (2019): 7–17. http://dx.doi.org/10.5922/2225-5346-2019-4-1.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
The conceptualization of the philosophy of the text requires a preliminary idea about the ways of the textual presentation of philosophy as such. At the same time, philosophical views per se are difficult to classify and systematize — at best, they are arranged by eras and cultural-ethnic factors. In this regard, it seems fruitful and justified not to build various rationalistic constructions but to take an open look at the very existence of philosophizing. From such perspectives, philosophy appears not so much a single, monolithic, and strictly ordered system as a ‘system of systems’ that are interrelated, interconnected, and reminiscent of Ludwig Wittgenstein's ‘family of language games’. Philosophy is a universal, ultimate understanding of the world, society, human beings, and their self-determination in this rea­lity. In this interpretation, being in itself appears as a text. Philosophizing as such is reali­zed in various forms of textualization, which are the focus of this article. Verbal textualization (sing­le words, paremia, aphoristics, parables, detailed plots, hermeneutic interpretations, con­ceptual systems) does not exclude visual, activity-driven textualizations and their mutual translations. Philosophy is capable of taking on diverse, dissimilar forms. It is as diversified as the paths of human self-determination, self-awareness, self-explanation, and self-justification. The­refore, the claims to exclusiveness and validity of any one way to textualize philosophizing do not seem justified.
35

Özgen, Mehmet Kasım. "The Philosophy of Self or Truth." Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy 5, no. 2 (December 31, 2015): 1. http://dx.doi.org/10.18491/bijop.62643.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
36

von der Luft, Eric. "Self and World in Schopenhauer’s Philosophy." International Studies in Philosophy 23, no. 2 (1991): 138–39. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/intstudphil199123263.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
37

Velleman, J. David. "From Self Psychology to Moral Philosophy." Nous 34, s14 (October 2000): 349–77. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/0029-4624.34.s14.18.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
38

Laursen, Simon. "SELF AND NATURE IN STOIC PHILOSOPHY." DANISH YEARBOOK OF PHILOSOPHY 28, no. 1 (August 2, 1993): 115–24. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/24689300_0280108.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
39

Wright, Tamra. "Self, Other, God: 20thCentury Jewish Philosophy." Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 74 (June 30, 2014): 149–69. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1358246114000137.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
AbstractMartin Buber, Franz Rosenzweig and Emmanuel Levinas are three of the most prominent Jewish philosophers of the 20thcentury. This paper looks at the different understandings each author offers of intersubjectivity and authentic self-hood and questions the extent to which for each author God plays a role in interpersonal relationships.
40

Morgan, Michael L. "Jewish Philosophy and Historical Self-Consciousness." Journal of Religion 71, no. 1 (January 1991): 36–49. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/488538.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
41

Bricke, J. "Review: Hume's Philosophy of the Self." Mind 113, no. 450 (April 1, 2004): 384–87. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/mind/113.450.384.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
42

Silverman, M. P. "Self-directed learning: Philosophy and implementation." Science and Education 5, no. 4 (October 1996): 357–80. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/bf00625607.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
43

Brown, Rachel. "The Emplotted Self: Self-Deception and Self-Knowledge." Philosophical Papers 32, no. 3 (November 2003): 279–300. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/05568640309485128.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
44

Garfield, Jay L. "A. C. Mukerji on the Problem of Skepticism and Its Resolution in Neo-Vedānta." International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 12, no. 1 (December 23, 2021): 90–100. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/22105700-bja10031.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
Abstract This paper examines the work of the unsung modern Indian Philosopher A. C. Mukerji, in his major works Self, Thought and Reality (1933) and The Nature of Self (1938). Mukerji constructs a skeptical challenge that emerges from the union of ideas drawn from early modern Europe, neo-Hegelian philosophy, and classical Buddhism and Vedānta. Mukerji’s worries about skepticism are important in part because they illustrate many of the creative tensions within the modern, synthetic period of Indian philosophy, and in part because they are truly profound, anticipating in interesting ways the worries that Feyerabend was to raise a few decades later. Arguing that Humean, Kantian, neo-Hegelian, and Buddhist philosophy each fail to provide an adequate account of self-knowledge, Mukerji leverages this finding to further argue that these systems fail to offer a proper account of knowledge more generally. His solution to skepticism centers on a distinctively modern interpretation of Śaṅkara’s Vedānta.
45

Weinstein, Nicole. "Self-sufficient." Nursery World 2022, no. 8 (August 2, 2022): 24–25. http://dx.doi.org/10.12968/nuwa.2022.8.24.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
46

Murtazaeva, Feruza Rashitovna. "PHILOSOPHY OF “FEMALE PROSE”." Scientific Reports of Bukhara State University 3, no. 3 (March 30, 2019): 195–98. http://dx.doi.org/10.52297/2181-1466/2019/3/3/12.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
The article considers “female prose” as a phenomenon. Of particular interest is the work of the bright Russian writer Victoria Tokareva. Tokareva is interested in such moral categories as mental uneasiness, the need for self-expression, the fear of loneliness. These categories are never addressed by low-quality, purely entertaining writers, where the reader becomes an “imaginer” or “dreamer,” a passive consumer and observer. Whose work can be attributed to the galaxy of Lyudmila Petrushevskaya, Tatyana Tolstoy, Lyudmila Ulitskaya, etc.
47

Chazan, Pauline. "Self-esteem, self-respect, and love of self: Ways of valuing the self." Philosophia 26, no. 1-2 (March 1998): 41–63. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/bf02380057.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
48

Mezei, Balazs. "Two Models of Radical Revelation in Austrian Philosophy." European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 1, no. 1 (March 21, 2009): 99–120. http://dx.doi.org/10.24204/ejpr.v1i1.332.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
In this paper I highlight two opposing models of the notion of divine revelation: the propositional and the radical. The propositional understanding of revelation was central to theology and philosophy until the 19th century. Since then, a number of other models of revelation have emerged. I define as radical the understanding of revelation which emphasizes two features of revelation: 1) God’s existence is *per se* revelatory; 2) God’s revelation is *per se* self-revelation. I propose too an assessment of the notion of propositional revelation as presented by Richard Swinburne. And I offer detailed analyses of two representatives of the early understanding of divine revelation as self-revelation: the views of Bernard Bolzano and Anton Günther. Bolzano, the renowned mathematician, was also a philosopher of religion; and Günther, one of the most ingenious writers in Austrian philosophy, was not only a theologian but also a philosopher comparable to the important figures of 19th century German thought.
49

Forgione, Luca. "Subject, Self-Consciousness, and Self-Knowledge in Kant’s Transcendental Philosophy." Studies in Transcendental Philosophy 3, no. 3 (2022): 0. http://dx.doi.org/10.18254/s271326680023706-6.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
Kant points to two forms of self-consciousness: the inner sense, or empirical apperception, based on a sensory form of self-awareness, and transcendental apperception. Through the notion of inner sense, Kant also allows for an introspective account of self-awareness; nonetheless, Kant holds an utterly sophisticated notion of basic self-consciousness provided for by the notion of transcendental apperception. As we will see, the doctrine of apperception is not to be confused with an introspective psychological approach: in reality, it is a formal model for the thinking activity itself which explains the most central concepts regarding subjecthood.
50

Feng, Cao. "Hengxian and Self-Generation." Journal of Chinese Philosophy 46, no. 1-2 (March 3, 2019): 58–77. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/15406253-0460102006.

Повний текст джерела
Стилі APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO та ін.
Анотація:
The abstruse phrase “Qi 氣is self-generating; constancy categorically does not engender Qi. Qi is self-generating and self-arising” in Hengxian 《恒先》 should be put in the context of the “self-generating” 自生 idea of Daoism. The cosmology depicted in the first part of Hengxian serves the political philosophy in the second part. “Qi is self-generating” serves the political philosophy of “non-action.” “Self-generating” is an important opinion in the philosophy of Daoism. However, the idea in ancient Daoist literature hasn’t been clearly analyzed. Hengxian shows that the idea of “self-generating” may have a long history and is related to the idea of “nature” 自然 in Laozi 《老子》 and Zhuangzi 《莊子》. “Self-generating” was inherited and developed by Yan Zun 嚴遵, Wang Chong 王充, Zheng Xuan 鄭玄, and Liezi 《列子》, and influenced Guo Xiang 郭象. The old “self-generating” theory based on Dao was developed into a new theory. Hengxian offers a precious resource for the ideological study of “self-generating.”

До бібліографії