Gotowa bibliografia na temat „Philosophy and religion”

Utwórz poprawne odniesienie w stylach APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard i wielu innych

Wybierz rodzaj źródła:

Zobacz listy aktualnych artykułów, książek, rozpraw, streszczeń i innych źródeł naukowych na temat „Philosophy and religion”.

Przycisk „Dodaj do bibliografii” jest dostępny obok każdej pracy w bibliografii. Użyj go – a my automatycznie utworzymy odniesienie bibliograficzne do wybranej pracy w stylu cytowania, którego potrzebujesz: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver itp.

Możesz również pobrać pełny tekst publikacji naukowej w formacie „.pdf” i przeczytać adnotację do pracy online, jeśli odpowiednie parametry są dostępne w metadanych.

Artykuły w czasopismach na temat "Philosophy and religion"

1

Strenski, Ivan. "Philosophy of (Lived) Religion". Studies in Religion/Sciences Religieuses 41, nr 1 (marzec 2012): 5–11. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0008429811430052.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
The cohabitation of philosophy with the study of religion has such a long history that we have not been motivated to consider the terms of that relationship. This paper proposes that this relationship needs to be examined radically. That is to say it proposes to query the nature, or possible natures, of the relationship of philosophy to the study of religion by posing such questions as the following: What kind of philosophy belongs in the study of religion? Constructive? Critical? Does philosophy have an independent role in the study of religion or does it, rather, best play the role of ‘handmaiden’? To the extent that philosophy plays an integral part in the study of religion, how should philosophy reflect the global and cross-cultural nature of the study of religion? To what extent does a philosophy that is integral to the study of religion need to change in order to reflect the philosophical agendas integral to other religions than Christianity? La cohabitation de la philosophie avec l’étude de la religion a une si longue histoire que nous ne nous sommes pas penchés sur les termes de cette relation. Cet article montre le besoin d’un examen radical de cette relation. C’est-à-dire qu’il propose d’interroger la nature, ou les natures possibles, de la relation que la philosophie entretient avec l’étude de la religion à partir de plusieurs questions: Quels types de philosophie font partie de l’étude de la religion? Constructive? Critique? La philosophie a-t-elle un rôle indépendant dans l’étude de la religion ou est-elle plutôt dans le rôle de « servir » ? Dans la mesure où la philosophie est une partie intégrante de l’étude de la religion, comment la philosophie devrait-elle refléter la nature mondiale et culturellement croisée de l’étude de la religion ? Dans quelle mesure, une philosophie faisant partie intégrante de l’étude de la religion doit-elle être transformée de façon à rendre compte des programmes des religions autres que la Chrétienté?
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
2

Rennie, Bryan. "The History (and Philosophy) of Religions". Studies in Religion/Sciences Religieuses 41, nr 1 (marzec 2012): 24–32. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0008429811430055.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
In a paper given at a Roundtable at the American Academy of Religion (AAR) National Annual Conference in Montreal in November of 2009, jointly organized by the North American Association for the Study of Religion and the Critical Theory and Discourses in Religion Group of the AAR, I argued for the ineluctably philosophical nature of what is most commonly called ‘method and theory in the study of religion.’ That paper ( Rennie, 2010 ) also argues that what is conventionally referred to as ‘philosophy of religion’ does not, strictly speaking, warrant that name since it is in fact a form of theology that utilizes philosophical methodologies to consider principally, if not exclusively, Christian concerns. I also argued that a philosophy of religion(s) constituted along the lines of the philosophy of science would be a potential improvement in both ‘philosophy of religion’ and ‘method and theory in the study of religion.’ In this paper I would like to consider—with the help of a closer look at contemporary philosophy of science—precisely what a reconstituted history (and philosophy) of religions might look like, how it might differ from current scholarship, and what it might achieve. Dans une communication donnée lors d’une table ronde à l’American Academy of Religion (AAR) National Annual Conference à Montréal en novembre 2009, organisée conjointement par le North American Association for the Study of Religion et le groupe de Critical Theory and Discourses in Religion de l’AAR, j’avais argué la nature inéluctablement philosophique de ce qui est couramment appelé « Method and Theory in the Study of Religion ». Cet article ( Rennie, 2010 ) soutient également la thèse que ce qu’on appelle couramment « Philosophie de la religion » ne correspond pas stricto sensu à ce qu’une telle dénomination recouvre puisqu’il s’agit en fait d’une forme de théologie recourant à des méthodes philosophiques pour envisager des préoccupations principalement, sinon exclusivement, chrétiennes. Je soutiens aussi qu’une philosophie des religions constituée à partir des lignes de force de la philosophie des sciences pourrait apporter une amélioration potentielle de la philosophie de la religion, de la méthode et de la théorie dans l’étude des religions. Dans cet article, j’aimerais examiner précisément —par le biais des apports de la philosophie des sciences contemporaine— ce à quoi l’histoire (et la philosophie) des religions pourrait ressembler, les termes dans lesquels elle se distinguerait des approches actuelles et ce à quoi nous pourrions ainsi aspirer.
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
3

Schilbrack, Kevin. "New Directions for Philosophy of Religion: Four Proposals". Studies in Religion/Sciences Religieuses 41, nr 1 (marzec 2012): 46–56. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0008429811430058.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
This set of papers explores the topic of “Possible Futures for Philosophy of Religion.” Though the field of philosophy of religion today has grown relatively narrow, these four papers seek to stretch it back out and all four are (as befitting our topic) forward-looking. Although the papers cover several different issues, I am going to shoehorn them into that pre-conceived category—the future of philosophy of religion—and then focus on the parts of the papers central to that category and ignore the other parts that don’t fit that template. This will not do justice to the complexity of the reality I am describing, but this procrustean practice is not unusual in philosophy of religion. Cette palette d’articles explore la thématique des ‘futurs possibles pour la philosophie des religions’. Bien que le champ de la philosophie des religions se soit aujourd’hui relativement rétréci, ces quatre articles tentent de l’élargir à nouveau et tous les quatre sont (au bénéfice de la thématique) tournés vers son devenir. Bien qu’ils couvrent des aspects différents de cette thématique, je vais les faire entrer dans cette catégorie préconçue —le futur de la philosophie des religions— et me focaliserai sur les parties des textes qui sont essentielles à cette catégorie pour en ignorer celles qui n’entrent pas dans ce cadre précis. Une telle approche ne saurait rendre compte de la complexité de la réalité que je décris, mais cette pratique de Procuste n’est point inhabituelle en philosophie des religions.
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
4

Bello, Joathas Soares. "Philosophy of religion and religation". Synesis 5, nr 2 (2013): 85–99. http://dx.doi.org/10.14195/1984-6754_5-2_6.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
5

Neville, Robert Cummings. "Religions, philosophies, and philosophy of religion". International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 38, nr 1-3 (grudzień 1995): 165–81. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/bf01322955.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
6

Allen, Diogenes. "IS Philosophy of Religion Enough?" Theology Today 44, nr 3 (październik 1987): 311–18. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/004057368704400303.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
“The adaptation and extension of the philosophy of religion required for teaching in theological seminaries would not only give it greater value to theological students. It could also lead to significant improvement of contemporary philosophy of religion itself, by showing the value of philosophical reflection on actual religions.”
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
7

Kazin, Aleksandar. "Russian religion and Russian philosophy". Zbornik Matice srpske za drustvene nauke, nr 152 (2015): 409–28. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/zmsdn1552409k.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
In the article the author tells us about the religious essence of Russian philosophy as its basic characteristic since in was founded in the middle of the 19th century until now. Russian philosophy never existed or couldn?t have existed in the European state of mind because it?s essentially a philosophic interpretation of religious faith. According to the author?s opinion, European philosophy, as a whole, has left the borders of the Christian spiritual plain by making the anthropocentric principle of thinking the absolute, which took it into positivism and nihilism. Russian philosophy hasn?t left the Christian spiritual field and has kept a theocentric (classical) type of thinking till the present day. The stand-point of the believing mind which rejects transcendental, as well as any other self foundation of the European philosophy. From the beginning until the present day, Russian philosophy has been opposed to the Descartes-Kant?s way of thinking. Western modern philosophy killed God intellectualy, and postmodern killed the Man as well, moving its philosophy into an empty space of ?transindividual constructions?. Ivan Kirejevski founded an ontological-gbnoseological model of Russian secular Christian philosophy in the middle of the 19th century, and from that, later, other branches of Russian philosophy developed: ontological-cultural (Danilevski, Leontjev), ontological-anthropological (Solovjov, Berdjajev, Ern). Briefly, Russian philosophy is what Russian national culture, based on Orthodox Christian views, can say about the World and the Man using the conceptual language.
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
8

Wood, William. "Leo Strauss on Religion as the Fundamental Alternative to Philosophy". Roczniki Filozoficzne 71, nr 2 (28.06.2023): 289–311. http://dx.doi.org/10.18290/rf237102.15.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
Leo Strauss is well known for his thesis that there is an irreconcilable conflict between philosophy and “revelation,” i.e. monotheistic revealed religion, which cannot be harmonized. The philosopher qua philosopher cannot be a believer, while the believer qua believer cannot be a philosopher. However, it is less widely recognized that Strauss’ thought about religion as the fundamental alternative to philosophy follows two divergent trajectories. The first emphasizes the unique importance of revealed religion, while the other emphasizes the conflict between philosophy and what he calls “religion in general.” Sometimes, Strauss suggests that revelation poses a unique “challenge” to philosophy, such that the philosopher must refute the mere possibility of revelation in order to justify the legitimacy of philosophy itself. Sometimes, however, he suggests rather that revelation is a religion like any other, not essentially different from e.g. ancient polytheism, which would seem therefore to pose no unique “challenge.” I argue that Strauss ultimately fails to reconcile these two strands of this thought and that this failure is related both to tensions internal to his positive conception of philosophy itself as a middle path between dogmatism and skepticism and to the fact that he begs the question by assuming, rather than proving, that it follows necessarily from “the very idea of revelation” that it cannot be harmonized with philosophy.
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
9

Obitts, Stanley. "Philosophy of Religion". Faith and Philosophy 4, nr 2 (1987): 224–25. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/faithphil19874221.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
10

Bleickert, Günter. "Philosophy of Religion". Philosophy and History 19, nr 1 (1986): 32–35. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/philhist198619119.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.

Rozprawy doktorskie na temat "Philosophy and religion"

1

Uhde, Bernhard. "Religions of Love? Reflections on religion and violence in the great monotheistic religions". Pontificia Universidad Católica del Perú - Departamento de Humanidades, 2012. http://repositorio.pucp.edu.pe/index/handle/123456789/113086.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
The great monotheistic religions –Judaism, Christianity, and Islam– agree in announcing God’s love for men, while demanding men’s love for God and for their neighbors. However, a brief look at these religions’ praxis leads to doubt whether this love is not a mere statement, while in history and at present were and are still imposed exclusive truth claims exercising violence against the adepts of the own religion (internally”) and, in especial, against the followers of other religions (externally”) in order to attain political power. Now, a distinction between the just sovereign power of God and detrimental violence should be made, asides from the fact that God’s sovereign power and God’s concept is not the same in the three great monotheistic religions. In Judaism God governs with love and as king, in Christianity with love and as servant, in Islam with love and majesty. Nevertheless, sovereign power is exclusive of God and detrimental violence is never desired among men. Only thus is power constitutive of religion’s inner nature, but not of the relation between religions or of religions with the world: There is no coercion in religion”.
Las grandes religiones monoteístas –Judaísmo, Cristianismo e Islam– coinciden en anunciar el amor de Dios a los hombres, y reclaman el amor de los hombres a Dios y al prójimo. Sin embargo, una breve mirada a la praxis de estas religiones hace dudar de si este amor no es una mera afirmación, mientras que en la historia y en el presente se impusieron y se imponen las pretensiones exclusivas de verdad mediante el ejercicio de la violencia en contra de los adeptos de la propia religión (internamente”) y, en especial, en contra de los seguidores de otras religiones (externamente”) para así alcanzar el poder político. Ahora bien, hay que distinguir entre el justo poder soberano de Dios y la violencia lesiva, además de que el poder soberano de Dios, al igual que el concepto de Dios, no es el mismo en las tres grandes religiones monoteístas. En el Judaísmo domina Dios con amor y como rey; en el Cristianismo, con amor y como servidor; en el Islam, con amor y majestad. Aunque siempre el poder soberano es exclusivo de Dios y nunca se desea la violencia lesiva entre los hombres. Solo así el poder es constitutivo de la naturaleza interna de la religión, mas no de la relación entre las religiones o de las religiones con el mundo: No hay coacción en la religión”.
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
2

Uhde, Bernhard. "Religions of Love? Reflections on Religion and Violence in the Great Monotheistic Religions". Pontificia Universidad Católica del Perú - Departamento de Humanidades, 2013. http://repositorio.pucp.edu.pe/index/handle/123456789/113277.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
The great monotheistic religions -Judaism, Christianity, and Islam- agree in announcing God's love for men, while demanding men's love for God and for their neighbors. However, a brief look at these religions' praxis leads to doubt whether this love is not a mere statement, while in history and at present were and are still imposed exclusive truth claims exercising violence against the adepts of the own religion (internally) and, in especial, against the followers of other religions (externally) in order to attain political power. Now, a distinction between the just sovereign power of God and detrimental violence should be made, asides from the fact that God's sovereign power and God's concept is not the same in the three great monotheistic religions. In Judaism God governs with love and as king, in Christianity with love and as servant, in Islam with love and majesty. Nevertheless, sovereign power is exclusive of God and detrimental violence is never desired among men. Only thus is power constitutive of religion's inner nature, but not of the relation between religions or of religions with the world: There is no coercion in religion.
Las grandes religiones monoteístas -Judaísmo, Cristianismo e Islam coincidenen anunciar el amor de Dios a los hombres, y reclaman el amor de los hombres a Dios y al prójimo. Sin embargo, una breve mirada a la praxis de estas religiones hace dudar de si este amor no es una mera afirmación, mientras que en la historia y en el presente se impusieron y se imponen laspretensiones exclusivas de verdad mediante el ejercicio de la violencia encontra de los adeptos de la propia religión (internamente) y, en especial, encontra de los seguidores de otras religiones (externamente) para así alcanzar el poder político. Ahora bien, hay que distinguir entre el justo poder soberano de Dios y la violencia lesiva, además de que el poder soberano de Dios, al igual que el concepto de Dios, no es el mismo en las tres grandes religiones monoteístas. En el Judaísmo domina Dios con amor y como rey; en el Cristianismo, con amor y como servidor; en el Islam, con amor y majestad. Aunque siempre el poder soberano es exclusivo de Dios y nunca se desea la violencia lesiva entre los hombres. Solo así el poder es constitutivo de la naturaleza intema de la religión, mas no de la relación entre las religiones o de las religiones con el mundo: No hay coacción en la religión
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
3

Kanaris, Jim. "Bernard Lonergan's philosophy of religion". Thesis, McGill University, 2000. http://digitool.Library.McGill.CA:80/R/?func=dbin-jump-full&object_id=36772.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
Describing Bernard Lonergan's relation to philosophy of religion is tricky business, with complications arising on different levels. To begin with, he does not use the term as it is usually understood in the field of the same name. Moreover, he addresses the same issues as philosophers of religion, but under the guise of philosophy of God or natural theology. Finally, he understands idiosyncratically the issue of religious experience, which is now a specialized category in philosophy of religion called upon to support formally rational statements for or against theistic belief. This central issue in Lonergan is further complicated by the fact that his idiosyncratic understanding of (religious) experience plays different roles in his thinking about God and religion. In this study I flesh out the dynamics of these various components, their interrelationships, and their function from early to late development.
My point of departure is a period in Lonergan's thought where he attributes more to the influence of religious experience in our thinking than at any time prior in his career. In chapter 1 I pursue some reasons that have been given for the tardiness of his response, intimating its nature and what it meant for his controversial "proof" for God's existence. Something of a detour is taken in chapter 2 since discussion of the concept of religious experience in Lonergan must grapple with what he means by experience in general. I decipher three senses to the term integral to his concept of consciousness that I distinguish from a contemporary model, that of David Chalmers. Since Lonergan is emphatic about distinguishing consciousness from its concept I trace this aspect of his philosophical claim against the background of Kant and Hegel, his main dialogue partners on the question. In chapter 3 I return to the specifically religious dimension of the notion of experience in the early Lonergan. Here I track the development of his category of religious experience as it moves from the periphery to the explanatory basis of his thought. In chapter 4 the relevant later literature in Lonergan is examined in which is seen the emergence of what is technically philosophy of religion to him. Among the distinctions I introduce is the difference between his model of religion and what he calls his philosophy of religion. Conceiving it historically, I see the former, his model of religion, as the departure point for what in his philosophy of religion he sets out to accomplish. They are related, of course, but not one and the same thing. To avoid confusion with the field of the same name, I recommend that we refer to his philosophy of religion as it is literally, as a philosophy of religious studies, distinguishing it firstly from his philosophy of God and secondly from his model of religious experience.
Besides providing an unprecedented comprehensive understanding of Lonergan's philosophy of religion, outlining the matter this way also aids in identifying precisely what are the points of contact between Lonergan's thoughts on God and religion and the issues presently discussed by philosophers of religion. The conclusion offers an example of this at the level of "philosophy of," the formal component of Lonergan's philosophy of religion in the generic sense in which I understand it. It represents steps toward a larger project, which I adumbrate in the appendix.
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
4

Merklinger, Philip M. "Philosophy, theology, and Hegel's Berlin philosophy of religion, 1821-1827". Thesis, University of Ottawa (Canada), 1991. http://hdl.handle.net/10393/7593.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
5

Levene, David Samuel. "Religion in Livy". Thesis, University of Oxford, 1989. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.305051.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
6

Robert, Dominique 1950. "Humane bioethics : medicine, philosophy, religion and law". Thesis, McGill University, 2001. http://digitool.Library.McGill.CA:80/R/?func=dbin-jump-full&object_id=31531.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
This thesis is about the content and concerns of each of four disciplines pertaining to the field of bioethics: medicine, philosophy, religion and law. Emphasis is put on the human values each reflects in patients' lives. A last chapter is dedicated to patients' narrative in order to bring a practical perspective to the discussions of the previous chapters. The four essential human values interconnecting among the four disciplines are: the patients' need for authority, the need for protection, the existential questioning about the meaning of life, and the fear of death.
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
7

Crowder, C. G. "Belief, unbelief and Wittgensteinian philosophy of religion". Thesis, Swansea University, 1993. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.636328.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
The interpretations of religious belief associated with philosophers in the Wittgensteinian tradition are widely misunderstood, as are the corresponding - but less well-known - interpretations of atheism. Instead of being a theory about autonomous 'language games', the Wittgensteinian approach is, in fact, a means of securing perspicuous representations of the relations between language and human practices; and the discourses of belief and unbelief are as rooted in our natural and cultural histories as any others. Foundationalist philosophers of religion isolate the discourses of belief and unbelief from human lives, both in describing the conflict between belief and unbelief and in attempting to arbitrate between the two. Assuming that metaphysical theism and atheism are fundamental to belief and unbelief, they advance a cognitivist and propositionalist analysis of both phenomena which is sometimes incoherent, and almost always impoverishing. Similarly, assuming that the conflict between belief and unbelief is a 'factual' one, they advocate ways of resolving it which betray a misunderstanding of the character of the conflict as it occurs in the lives of believers and atheists. The design argument, past and present, is a case in point: natural theology and natural atheology prove to be alike in misrepresenting perspectives upon the world as inferences drawn from it. Hume's Dialogues demonstrate the sheer irrelevance of the latter to the conflict between belief and unbelief, and compel us to reflect upon that conflict in different ways.
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
8

Wodzinski, Phillip David. "Kant's Doctrine of Religion as Political Philosophy". Thesis, Boston College, 2009. http://hdl.handle.net/2345/987.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
Thesis advisor: Susan Shell
Through a close reading of Immanuel Kant's late book, Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, the dissertation clarifies the political element in Kant's doctrine of religion and so contributes to a wider conception of his political philosophy. Kant's political philosophy of religion, in addition to extending and further animating his moral doctrine, interprets religion in such a way as to give the Christian faith a moral grounding that will make possible, and even be an agent of, the improvement of social and political life. The dissertation emphasizes the wholeness and structure of Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason as a book, for the teaching of the book is not exhausted by the articulation of its doctrine but also includes both the fact and the manner of its expression: the reader learns most fully from Kant by giving attention to the structure and tone of the book as well as to its stated content and argumentation. The Religion provides the basis not only for a proposed reenvisioning of the basis of existing religious creeds and practices, but along with this a devastating critique of them in particularly moral terms. This, however, is only half of what constitutes Kant's political philosophy of religion; Kant goes beyond the philosophical analysis of the social-political context of religion and pursues, alongside this effort, a political presentation of philosophy which is intended to relieve the reader's anxieties concerning the tension between philosophy and political life that it is in the interest of the partisans of the church-faith to encourage
Thesis (PhD) — Boston College, 2009
Submitted to: Boston College. Graduate School of Arts and Sciences
Discipline: Political Science
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
9

Chetelat, James Pierre. "Hegel's concept of religion". Thesis, McGill University, 2008. http://digitool.Library.McGill.CA:80/R/?func=dbin-jump-full&object_id=18726.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
In this dissertation I explore how Hegel conceives of the practice of religion. Religion for Hegel cannot be the relationship between humans and a transcendent being, since, as I argue, Hegel's God is not a being of the transcendent sort, but reason as Idea and spirit. Nor does Hegel primarily understand religion as feeling or immediate experience of the divine. According to Hegel, religion involves knowledge of the truth in the form of representation, and I discuss the truths that in his view are common to all religions, as well as the principle that he thinks guides the development of the various determinate religions that culminate in Christianity. But, first and foremost, religion for Hegel is cultus or practice in which a person overcomes her own particularity in a radical manner and identifies completely with the universal, objective standpoint. By overcoming her particularity, the person recognizes that her own interests lack absolute value, and she is willing to abandon them entirely for the sake of what the universal requires of her. The highest form of the cultus for Hegel is full participation in Sittlichkeit, or the social and cultural life of modern Protestant Europe. In the cultus, a person achieves freedom, the goal of religion and the highest value in Hegel's philosophy. I argue that freedom for Hegel is independence vis-à-vis the world in both an active and a passive sense. As active, freedom is the autonomy that a person possesses when she acts rationally or follows the ethical norms that are a necessary moment of being free. As passive, freedom is the independence that a person gains when she is no longer attached to her particular interests and is accepting of circumstances in which her desires are not met. But for Hegel the norms of freedom also allow and require that a person continue to engage fully in the world and actively pursue her own particular interests, since such activities play a necessary role in being free. In my
J'explore dans cette thèse la manière dont Hegel conçoit la pratique religieuse. Pour Hegel, la religion ne saurait être une relation entre un être transcendant et les humains puisque, ainsi que je le démontre, le dieu hégélien n'est pas un tel être transcendant mais plutôt la raison en tant qu'Idée et esprit. Il n'est pas non plus question pour Hegel de comprendre la religion comme le sentiment ou l'expérience immédiate du divin. Selon lui, la religion implique une connaissance de la vérité sous la forme d'une représentation. Mon propos à cet égard est de cerner les vérités qui, de son point de vue, sont communes à toutes les religions, et d'identifier le principe qui, selon lui, préside au développement des diverses religions déterminées qui culminent dans le christianisme. Mais, d'abord et avant tout, la religion est pour Hegel un culte ou une pratique par laquelle une personne surmonte de manière radicale sa propre particularité et s'identifie complètement au point de vue universel et objectif. En surmontant sa particularité, cette personne reconnaît que ses intérêts sont dépourvus de valeur absolue et accepte de les abandonner entièrement pour se soumettre aux exigences de l'universel. Selon Hegel, la forme la plus élevée du culte est une participation pleine et entière à la Sittlichkeit, ou à la vie sociale et culturelle de l'Europe protestante moderne. Le culte permet à celui qui y participe de parvenir à la liberté, but de la religion et valeur ultime dans la philosophie hégélienne. J'argumente que la liberté est pour Hegel une indépendance, tant active que passive, vis-à-vis du monde externe. En tant qu'elle est active, la liberté est l'autonomie qu'une personne possède lorsqu'elle agit rationnellement ou qu'elle se conforme aux normes éthiques qui constituent un moment nécessaire de son être-libre. En tant qu'elle est passive, la liberté est l'indépendance qu'une personne atteint lorsqu'elle s'est$
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
10

Rochard, Michelle A. "Kant's philosophy of religion : the relationship between Ecclesiastical faith and reasoned religion". Thesis, National Library of Canada = Bibliothèque nationale du Canada, 1998. http://www.collectionscanada.ca/obj/s4/f2/dsk2/tape15/PQDD_0005/MQ39436.pdf.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.

Książki na temat "Philosophy and religion"

1

Wilfried, Schröder, red. Natural science, philosophy, and religion =: Naturwissenschaft, Philosophie und Religion. [Bremen]: Science Edition, 2006.

Znajdź pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
2

Yandell, Keith E. Philosophy of Religion. London: Taylor & Francis Group Plc, 2004.

Znajdź pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
3

Geisler, Norman L. Philosophy of religion. Wyd. 2. Grand Rapids, Mich: Baker Book House, 1988.

Znajdź pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
4

Meister, Chad. Philosophy of Religion. London: Palgrave Macmillan UK, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/9781137314758.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
5

J, Wainwright William, red. Philosophy of religion. New York: Routledge, 2009.

Znajdź pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
6

1917-, Devaraja N. K., i Indian Institute of Advanced Study., red. Philosophy and religion. Shimla: Indian Institute of Advanced Study in association with Indus Pub. Co., 1989.

Znajdź pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
7

Wainwright, William J. Philosophy of religion. Wyd. 2. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Pub., 1999.

Znajdź pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
8

Martin, Warner, red. Religion and philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.

Znajdź pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
9

Guttorm, Fløistad, red. Philosophy of religion. Dordrecht: Springer, 2010.

Znajdź pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
10

W, Perrett Roy, red. Philosophy of religion. New York: Garland, 2000.

Znajdź pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.

Części książek na temat "Philosophy and religion"

1

Greetham, Bryan. "Religion". W Philosophy, 154–67. London: Palgrave Macmillan UK, 2006. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-72563-2_12.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
2

Parekh, Bhikhu. "Philosophy of Religion". W Gandhi’s Political Philosophy, 65–84. London: Palgrave Macmillan UK, 1989. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-09248-2_4.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
3

Dawes, Gregory W. "Philosophy and Religion". W Religion, Philosophy and Knowledge, 1–4. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-43500-8_1.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
4

Peperzak, Adriaan. "Philosophy — religion — theology". W Issues in Contemporary Philosophy of Religion, 29–39. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 2001. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0516-6_3.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
5

Geach, Peter. "Philosophy of Religion". W Peter Geach: Philosophical Encounters, 213–14. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 1991. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7885-1_16.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
6

Morreall, John. "Philosophy and religion". W The Primer of Humor Research, 211–42. Berlin, New York: Mouton de Gruyter, 2008. http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/9783110198492.211.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
7

Xu, Guobin, Yanhui Chen i Lianhua Xu. "Philosophy and Religion". W Understanding Chinese Culture, 1–27. Singapore: Springer Singapore, 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-981-10-8162-0_1.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
8

Taliaferro, Charles. "Philosophy of Religion". W The Blackwell Companion to the Study of Religion, 123–45. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781405168748.ch6.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
9

Randau, Henk R., i Olga Medinskaya. "Philosophy and Religion". W China Business 2.0, 205–6. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-07677-5_39.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
10

Baggini, Julian, i Gareth Southwell. "Philosophy of Religion". W Philosophy: Key Themes, 120–46. London: Palgrave Macmillan UK, 2012. http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/9781137008879_5.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.

Streszczenia konferencji na temat "Philosophy and religion"

1

Khitruk, Ekaterina. "Публичное и частное в философии религии Ричарда Рорти". W The Public/Private in Modern Civilization, the 22nd Russian Scientific-Practical Conference (with international participation) (Yekaterinburg, April 16-17, 2020). Liberal Arts University – University for Humanities, Yekaterinburg, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.35853/ufh-public/private-2020-14.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
The article covers the religious conception in the work of the famous American philosopher Richard Rorty. The author emphasises the secular and finalist views of R. Rorty on the nature of religion, and on the philosopher’s gradual perception of the need for their creative reinterpretation due to the actualisation of the role of religion in intellectual and political spheres. The article uncovers two fundamental constituents of Richard Rorty’s religious philosophy. The first of them is associated with R. Rorty’s perception of the ‘weak thinking’ concept in the writings of Italian philosopher Gianni Vattimo. R. Rorty holds ‘weak thinking’ and ‘kenosis’ to be the key to understanding the possibility of religion in the postmodern era. The second aspect concerns the existence of religion in the public space. Here the distinction between ‘strong’ narratives and ‘weak’ thinking correlates with the politically significant distinction between ‘strong’ religious institutions and private (parish, community) religious practice. Rorty believes that the activity of ‘strong’ religious structures threatens liberal ‘social hope’ on the gradual democratisation of mankind. The article concludes that Richard Rorty’s philosophy of religion presents an original conception of religion in the context of modern temporal humanism; the concept positively evaluates religious experience to the extent that it does not become a basis for theoretical and political manipulations on the part of ‘strong’ religious institutes.
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
2

Visweswaran, HV. "Philosophy of India-Dravidology". W The Asian Conference on Ethics, Religion & Philosophy 202. The International Academic Forum(IAFOR), 2021. http://dx.doi.org/10.22492/issn.2187-476x.2021.7.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
3

Sasaki, Kei. "Life in Philosophy and Religion, and Beyond". W Annual International Conference on Philosophy: Yesterday, Today & Tomorrow (PYTT 2016). Global Science & Technology Forum (GSTF), 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.5176/2382-5677_pytt16.17.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
4

Macaraan, Willard Enrique R. "Exploring the Social Space of Filipino Catholics in Japan: [De]Ghettoization". W The Asian Conference on Ethics, Religion & Philosophy 2023. The International Academic Forum(IAFOR), 2023. http://dx.doi.org/10.22492/issn.2187-476x.2023.6.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
5

Li, Chen-Mei, Li-Yueh Chen Andy i Kuo-Chin Shih. "Transcending Time and Space: The Social Practice of Weixin Shengjiao in Facing Global Ethical Responsibility". W The Asian Conference on Ethics, Religion & Philosophy 2023. The International Academic Forum(IAFOR), 2023. http://dx.doi.org/10.22492/issn.2187-476x.2023.10.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
6

Usenco, Dmitry. "Polytheism and Monotheism: Mutually Exclusive or Interdependent?" W The Asian Conference on Ethics, Religion & Philosophy 2023. The International Academic Forum(IAFOR), 2023. http://dx.doi.org/10.22492/issn.2187-476x.2023.1.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
7

Cowie, Iain F. "Western Diplomacy’s Ineffective Iconoclasm: Conflict Resolution With China and the West’s Forgotten Rhetorical Tools". W The Asian Conference on Ethics, Religion & Philosophy 2023. The International Academic Forum(IAFOR), 2023. http://dx.doi.org/10.22492/issn.2187-476x.2023.8.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
8

Iwanaga, Yohei. "Mechanisms and Ethics of Sustainable Exchange: Interaction and Sympathy in Relationship Marketing". W The Asian Conference on Ethics, Religion & Philosophy 2023. The International Academic Forum(IAFOR), 2023. http://dx.doi.org/10.22492/issn.2187-476x.2023.2.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
9

Li, Chen-Mei, Yu-Shan Yen i Meng-Chen Wu. "Lifelong Learning as a Key to the 21st Century: I Ching Education as an Example". W The Asian Conference on Ethics, Religion & Philosophy 2023. The International Academic Forum(IAFOR), 2023. http://dx.doi.org/10.22492/issn.2187-476x.2023.11.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
10

Shamoa-Nir, Lipaz. "Examining Dialogic Opportunities in Higher Education: Lessons Learned From Dialogue Courses for Jewish Students". W The Asian Conference on Ethics, Religion & Philosophy 2023. The International Academic Forum(IAFOR), 2023. http://dx.doi.org/10.22492/issn.2187-476x.2023.5.

Pełny tekst źródła
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.

Raporty organizacyjne na temat "Philosophy and religion"

1

HEFNER, Robert. IHSAN ETHICS AND POLITICAL REVITALIZATION Appreciating Muqtedar Khan’s Islam and Good Governance. IIIT, październik 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.47816/01.001.20.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
Ours is an age of pervasive political turbulence, and the scale of the challenge requires new thinking on politics as well as public ethics for our world. In Western countries, the specter of Islamophobia, alt-right populism, along with racialized violence has shaken public confidence in long-secure assumptions rooted in democracy, diversity, and citizenship. The tragic denouement of so many of the Arab uprisings together with the ascendance of apocalyptic extremists like Daesh and Boko Haram have caused an even greater sense of alarm in large parts of the Muslim-majority world. It is against this backdrop that M.A. Muqtedar Khan has written a book of breathtaking range and ethical beauty. The author explores the history and sociology of the Muslim world, both classic and contemporary. He does so, however, not merely to chronicle the phases of its development, but to explore just why the message of compassion, mercy, and ethical beauty so prominent in the Quran and Sunna of the Prophet came over time to be displaced by a narrow legalism that emphasized jurisprudence, punishment, and social control. In the modern era, Western Orientalists and Islamists alike have pushed the juridification and interpretive reification of Islamic ethical traditions even further. Each group has asserted that the essence of Islam lies in jurisprudence (fiqh), and both have tended to imagine this legal heritage on the model of Western positive law, according to which law is authorized, codified, and enforced by a leviathan state. “Reification of Shariah and equating of Islam and Shariah has a rather emaciating effect on Islam,” Khan rightly argues. It leads its proponents to overlook “the depth and heights of Islamic faith, mysticism, philosophy or even emotions such as divine love (Muhabba)” (13). As the sociologist of Islamic law, Sami Zubaida, has similarly observed, in all these developments one sees evidence, not of a traditionalist reassertion of Muslim values, but a “triumph of Western models” of religion and state (Zubaida 2003:135). To counteract these impoverishing trends, Khan presents a far-reaching analysis that “seeks to move away from the now failed vision of Islamic states without demanding radical secularization” (2). He does so by positioning himself squarely within the ethical and mystical legacy of the Qur’an and traditions of the Prophet. As the book’s title makes clear, the key to this effort of religious recovery is “the cosmology of Ihsan and the worldview of Al-Tasawwuf, the science of Islamic mysticism” (1-2). For Islamist activists whose models of Islam have more to do with contemporary identity politics than a deep reading of Islamic traditions, Khan’s foregrounding of Ihsan may seem unfamiliar or baffling. But one of the many achievements of this book is the skill with which it plumbs the depth of scripture, classical commentaries, and tasawwuf practices to recover and confirm the ethic that lies at their heart. “The Quran promises that God is with those who do beautiful things,” the author reminds us (Khan 2019:1). The concept of Ihsan appears 191 times in 175 verses in the Quran (110). The concept is given its richest elaboration, Khan explains, in the famous hadith of the Angel Gabriel. This tradition recounts that when Gabriel appeared before the Prophet he asked, “What is Ihsan?” Both Gabriel’s question and the Prophet’s response make clear that Ihsan is an ideal at the center of the Qur’an and Sunna of the Prophet, and that it enjoins “perfection, goodness, to better, to do beautiful things and to do righteous deeds” (3). It is this cosmological ethic that Khan argues must be restored and implemented “to develop a political philosophy … that emphasizes love over law” (2). In its expansive exploration of Islamic ethics and civilization, Khan’s Islam and Good Governance will remind some readers of the late Shahab Ahmed’s remarkable book, What is Islam? The Importance of Being Islamic (Ahmed 2016). Both are works of impressive range and spiritual depth. But whereas Ahmed stood in the humanities wing of Islamic studies, Khan is an intellectual polymath who moves easily across the Islamic sciences, social theory, and comparative politics. He brings the full weight of his effort to conclusion with policy recommendations for how “to combine Sufism with political theory” (6), and to do so in a way that recommends specific “Islamic principles that encourage good governance, and politics in pursuit of goodness” (8).
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
2

Lyzanchuk, Vasyl. THE CHARITABLE ENERGY OF THE JOURNALISTIC WORD. Ivan Franko National University of Lviv, luty 2022. http://dx.doi.org/10.30970/vjo.2022.51.11415.

Pełny tekst źródła
Streszczenie:
The article investigates the immortality of books, collections, including those, translated into foreign languages, composed of the publications of publications of worldview journalism. It deals with top analytics on simulated training of journalists, the study of events and phenomena at the macro level, which enables the qualitative forecast of world development trends in the appropriate contexts for a long time. Key words: top, analytics, book, worldview journalism, culture, arguments, forecast.The article is characterized intellectual-spiritual, moral-aesthetic and information-educational values of of scientific and journalistic works of Professor Mykola Hryhorchuk “Where are you going, Ukraine?” and “Freedom at the Barricades”. Mykola Ivanovych’s creative informational and educational communication are reviews, reviews, reviews and current works of writers, poets, publicists. Such as Maria Matios, Vira Vovk, Roman Ivanychuk, Dmytro Pavlychko, Yuriy Shcherban, Bohdan Korsak, Hryhoriy Huseynov, Vasyl Ruban, Yaroslav Melnyk, Sofia Andrukhovych. His journalistic reflections are about memorable events of the recent past for Ukrainians and historical figures are connected with them. It is emphasized that in his books Mykola Hryhorchuk convincingly illuminates the way to develop a stable Ukrainian immunity, national identity, development and strengthening of the conciliar independent state in the fight against the eternal Moscow enemy. Among the defining ideological and political realization of the National Idea of Ukrainian statehood, which are mentioned in the scientific and journalistic works of M. Hryhorchuk, the fundamental ones – linguistic and religious – are singled out. Israel and Poland are a clear example for Ukrainians. In these states, language and religion were absolutized and it is thanks to this understanding of the essence of state-building and national identity that it is contrary to many difficulties achieve the desired life-affirming goal. The author emphasizes that any information in the broadest and narrow sense can be perceived without testing for compliance with the moral and spiritual mission of man, the fundamental values of the Ukrainian ethnic group, putting moral and spiritual values in the basis of state building. The outstanding Ukrainian philosopher Hryhoriy Skovoroda emphasized: “Faith is the light that sees in the darkness…” Books by physicist Mykola Hryhorchuk “Where are you going, Ukraine?” and “Freedom at the Barricades” are illuminated by faith in the Victory over the bloody centuries-old Moscow darkness.
Style APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO itp.
Oferujemy zniżki na wszystkie plany premium dla autorów, których prace zostały uwzględnione w tematycznych zestawieniach literatury. Skontaktuj się z nami, aby uzyskać unikalny kod promocyjny!

Do bibliografii