Littérature scientifique sur le sujet « Medicine – Philosophy – History »
Créez une référence correcte selon les styles APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard et plusieurs autres
Consultez les listes thématiques d’articles de revues, de livres, de thèses, de rapports de conférences et d’autres sources académiques sur le sujet « Medicine – Philosophy – History ».
À côté de chaque source dans la liste de références il y a un bouton « Ajouter à la bibliographie ». Cliquez sur ce bouton, et nous générerons automatiquement la référence bibliographique pour la source choisie selon votre style de citation préféré : APA, MLA, Harvard, Vancouver, Chicago, etc.
Vous pouvez aussi télécharger le texte intégral de la publication scolaire au format pdf et consulter son résumé en ligne lorsque ces informations sont inclues dans les métadonnées.
Articles de revues sur le sujet "Medicine – Philosophy – History"
Maluleka, P., et T. Mathebula. « Trends in African philosophy and their implications for the Africanisation of the South Africa history caps curriculum : a case study of Odera Oruka philosophy ». Yesterday and Today 27 (2022) : 65–89. http://dx.doi.org/10.17159/2223-0386/2022/n27a3.
Texte intégralBorkowska, Katarzyna. « Historia medycyny na pograniczu dziedzin. Rozważania na marginesie książki Medicina, antiqua mediaevalis et moderna. Historia – filozofia – religia, red. S. Konarska-Zimnicka, L. Kostuch i B. Wojciechowska, Kielce 2019 ». Kwartalnik Historii Nauki i Techniki, no 4 (2020) : 135–43. http://dx.doi.org/10.4467/0023589xkhnt.20.032.12865.
Texte intégralKaufman, Igor S. « Philosophy of medicine and historiography of medicine ». Vestnik of Samara State Technical University. Series Philosophy 4, no 2 (29 juillet 2022) : 64–68. http://dx.doi.org/10.17673/vsgtu-phil.2022.2.7.
Texte intégralRadu, Mirela. « Medicine versus philosophy ». Romanian Journal of Military Medicine 120, no 2 (2 août 2017) : 32–36. http://dx.doi.org/10.55453/rjmm.2017.120.2.5.
Texte intégralLongrigg, James. « Presocratic Philosophy and Hippocratic Medicine ». History of Science 27, no 1 (mars 1989) : 1–39. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/007327538902700101.
Texte intégralOparin, O. A. « Medicine in the Byzantine empire : history and philosophy ». Shidnoevropejskij zurnal vnutrisnoi ta simejnoi medicini 2020, no 2b (décembre 2020) : 70–96. http://dx.doi.org/10.15407/internalmed2020.02b.070.
Texte intégralTrochimska-Kubacka, Beata. « Andrzeja J. Norasa badania nad neokantyzmem ». Studia Philosophica Wratislaviensia 16, no 2 (2 décembre 2021) : 131–41. http://dx.doi.org/10.19195/1895-8001.16.2.10.
Texte intégralMu, XiYeLe, Lan Feng, Na Ta, Li Bai, RuRe A, GenNa Ba et MingHai Fu. « History, philosophy and modern research of traditional Mongolian medicine ». History and Philosophy of Medicine 4, no 4 (2022) : 22. http://dx.doi.org/10.53388/hpm20221001022.
Texte intégralNowak, Witold. « Stefan Harassek and the problems of contemporary philosophy ». Galicja. Studia i materiały 8 (2022) : 248–63. http://dx.doi.org/10.15584/galisim.2022.8.17.
Texte intégralBastian, Misty L., M. Akin Makinde et Daniel A. Offiong. « African Philosophy, Culture, and Traditional Medicine ». Journal of Religion in Africa 24, no 1 (février 1994) : 66. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/1581377.
Texte intégralThèses sur le sujet "Medicine – Philosophy – History"
Kassell, Lauren. « Simon Forman's philosophy of medicine : medicine, astrology and alchemy in London, c.1580-1611 ». Thesis, University of Oxford, 1997. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.270851.
Texte intégralNormandin, Sebastien. « Visions of vitalism : medicine, philosophy and the soul in nineteenth century France ». Thesis, McGill University, 2005. http://digitool.Library.McGill.CA:80/R/?func=dbin-jump-full&object_id=100666.
Texte intégralI argue that the decline of medical vitalism was brought about by the rise of scientific medicine, the experimentalism of physiologists like Claude Bernard and the growing influence of positivism in late 19th century France. I see the seminal moment of this transition from a metaphysical to a scientific world-view in the materialism-spiritualism controversy of the 1850s, which was sparked by the development of modern biology and the experimental life sciences.
Despite its general disappearance from mainstream medicine and science, vitalism continued to have echoes in a number of fields in the 20th century, and remains a concept relevant to our contemporary circumstances.
Shelton, Paul Hunter. « The cook as physician : medical philosophy, nutrition, and diet in England, 1450-1650 / ». Thesis, This resource online, 1990. http://scholar.lib.vt.edu/theses/available/etd-08182009-040212/.
Texte intégralWalmsley, Jonathan Craig. « John Locke's natural philosophy (1632-1671) ». Thesis, Boston Spa, U.K. : British Library Document Supply Centre, 1998. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?did=1&uin=uk.bl.ethos.286485.
Texte intégralRossouw, Theresa Marie. « A dialectical interpretation of the history of Western medicine : perspectives, problems and possibilities ». Thesis, Stellenbosch : Stellenbosch University, 2003. http://hdl.handle.net/10019.1/53240.
Texte intégralENGLISH ABSTRACT: The health of the medical profession hangs in the balance. Scepticism, mistrust and legal restraints have entered its hallowed corridors and are threatening its integrity and independence. There are myriad seemingly intractable moral dilemmas that doctors, ethicists and judges are trying to resolve with the aid of available principles and rules of ethical discourse; yet, the answers remain elusive. Hegel, the eighteenth century philosopher, postulated that perplexity only exists because we do not look at the world correctly: because we tend to think in an oppositional way, we abstract from the complex interrelation of things. He therefore suggested that one should step back and think reflectively about the problem and seek the one-sided assumptions that led to the impasse. My proposition is that at the heart of many of the current medical dilemmas lies the opposition between paternalism and autonomy. These two fundamental concepts arose out of two different traditions, and now, because they have been abstracted from the contexts and histories that inform them, seem to be diametrically opposed. Paternalism arose out of the ethics of competence that originated in ancient Greece. The art of medicine was still in its infancy and physicians had to prove their ability and benevolence to a mistrustful public. Demonstration of competence became a necessary component of any successful practice. As the power of medicine grew with the scientific and technological advances of the Enlightenment, professionals' authority and competence were reinforced and systematically fostered a paternalistic attitude at the expense of adequate protection of the individual. In response to the power differential found in the political and social arena, individual human rights were promulgated in the eighteenth century. In the medical sphere, the culture of rights was translated into, among others, the fundamental right to autonomy. Patients now have the right to decide on interventions and treatment in accordance with their own conception of a good life. Paternalism thus developed out of a societal system that embraced the virtues and communal responsibility within the bounds of the polis of antiquity; autonomy arose out of the designs of the Enlightenment where the individual was hailed supreme. Remnants of both traditions are evident in contemporary medicine, but they have been abstracted from their original purpose and meaning, leading to perplexity and antagonism. Following the Hegelian method of dialectic, I postulate a thesis of paternalism, and in response to this, an antithesis of autonomy. I attempt to show that an intransigent insistence on one side or the other will only serve to strengthen the paradox and fail to lead to an acceptable solution. I aim to develop a synthesis where both concepts are embraced with the help ofa better understanding of human nature and the inevitable limits of human knowledge. Influenced by the work of the psychoanalyst Carl Jung, I firstly argue for the existence of a biological human need for compassion and thus the importance of virtue ethics, which embraces this need. Secondly, focusing on the ethics of futurity developed by Hans Jonas, I delineate the altered nature of human action and the derivative need for an ethics of responsibility. I propose possibilities for the future based on the ideas of compassion, virtue and responsibility and argue that they can only be reconciled in a pluralistic ethic.
AFRIKAANSE OPSOMMING: Die mediese professie het'n dokter nodig. Een wat kan sin maak van die wantroue en vyandigheid wat te bespeur is in die pasient-dokter verhouding en wat toepaslike terapie kan voorskryf Al die pogings tot behandeling deur middel van reëls, regulasies en etiese kodes het tot dusver misluk en het vele skynbaar-onoplosbare morele dilemmas agtergelaat. Die Duitse filosoof, Hegel, het in die agtiende eeu aangevoer dat verwarring onstaan bloot omdat ons die wêreld op die verkeerde wyse beskou: die mens is geneig tot opposisionele denke en neem daarom nie die komplekse onderlinge verbintenisse van die onderskeie elemente in ag nie. Hegel het dus voorgestel dat wanneer ons met sulke hardnekkige situasies gekonfronteer word, ons 'n tree terug neem en die situasie reflektiewelik ondersoek vir eensydige veronderstellings. My hipotese is dat baie van die etiese dilemmas wat op die oomblik in medisyne voorkom, voortvloei uit die opposisie tussen paternalisme en outonomitiet. Hierdie twee fundamentele beginsels het uit twee verskillende tradisies ontstaan en nou, omdat hulle nie meer in hulle oorspronklike konteks voorkom nie, vertoon hulle skynbaar teenstellend. Paternalisme het onstaan vanuit die etiek van bevoegdheid wat teruggevoer kan word na die tyd van Hippocrates. Medisyne was 'n nuwe professie wat nog sy eerbaarheid en welwillendheid aan 'n wantrouige publiek moes bewys. Bevoegdheid was dus 'n essensiële komponent van enige suksesvolle praktyk. Indrukwekkende vooruitgang in die dissiplines van wetenskap en tegnologie sedert die agtiende eeu het dokters se gesag en bevoegdheid bevorder en stelselmatig 'n paternalistiese houding gekweek ten koste van toepaslike beskerming van die individu. In respons tot die magsverskil in die politieke en sosiale sfeer het 'n beweging in hierdie tyd ontstaan om universêle mensseregte te bewerkstellig. In medisyne het hierdie regsbeweging gekulmineer in, onder andere, die fundamentele reg tot self-beskikking - in ander woorde, outonomiteit. Die pasient is dus nou geregtig daarop om selfte besluit oor ingrepe en behandeling op grond van sylhaar konsep van 'n goeie en sinvolle lewe. Paternalisme het dus ontstaan uit 'n samelewing waar die deugte en gemeenskapsverantwoordelikhede integraal was tot die funksionering van die polis; outonomie aan die ander kant, het ontstaan uit die idees van Die Verligting waar die individu as belangriker as die gemeenskap geag is. Volgens die Hegeliaanse dialektiese metode, postuleer ek dus 'n tesis van paternalisme en in respons daartoe, 'n antitese van outonomiteit. Ek voer aan dat 'n eiewillige aandrang op een of die ander die dilemma net sal verdiep. Ek poog dus om 'n sintese te ontwikkel wat albei konsepte inkorporeer met behulp van 'n analise van die aard van die mens en die noodwendige beperkinge van sy kennis. Geskool op die werk van die psigoanalis Carl Jung, bespreek ek die mens se biologiese behoefte aan medelye en stel dus die saak vir die belang van 'n etiek van deugte wat hierdie behoefte onderskraag. Tweedens, beinvloed deur die etiek van die toekoms, soos beskryf deur Hans Jonas, ontwikkel ek die idee van die gewysigde skaal van menslike dade en gevolglik die noodsaklikheid van 'n etiek van verantwoordelikheid. Ek postuleer dus 'n benadering wat wentel om die konsepte van medelye, deug en verantwoordelikheid wat slegs in die vorm van 'n pluralistiese etiek tot uiting kan kom.
Dyde, Sean Kieran. « Brains, minds and nerves in British medicine and physiology, 1764-1852 ». Thesis, University of Cambridge, 2014. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.648694.
Texte intégralShillito, Alex Benjamin. « How the Heart Became Muscle : From René Descartes to Nicholas Steno ». Scholar Commons, 2019. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/7939.
Texte intégralHolman, Bennett Harvey. « The fundamental antagonism| science and commerce in medical epistemology ». Thesis, University of California, Irvine, 2015. http://pqdtopen.proquest.com/#viewpdf?dispub=3727347.
Texte intégralI consider the claims made by medical ethicists that funding by pharmaceutical companies threaten the integrity of medical research and the claims of philosophers of science that evidence-based medicine can provide a sound epistemic foundation on which to base medical treatment decisions. Drawing on both game theory and medical history, I argue that both medical ethicists and philosophers of science have missed crucial aspects of medical research. I show that both veritistic and commercial aims are enduring and entrenched aspects of medical research. Because these two drives are perpetually pulling medical research in different directions, I identify the resultant conflict as the fundamental antagonism
The primary task of the dissertation is to provide a framework that incorporates both drivers of medical research. Specifically, I argue that medical research is best conceived of as an asymmetric arms race. Such a dynamic is typified by a series of moves and countermoves between competing parties who are adjusting to one another's behavior, in this case between those who seek to make medical practice more responsive to good evidence and those whose primary motivations are instead commercial in character.
Such a model presents three challenges to standard evidential hierarchies which equate epistemic reliability with methodological rigor. The first is to show that reliability and rigor can (and do) come apart as a result of the countermeasures employed by manufactures. This fact suggests that in considering policy proposals to improve epistemic reliability, it is robustness (i.e. resistance to manipulation) that should be the crucial desideratum. The second consequence is a reorientation of medical epistemology. One of the primary strategies that manufacturers have employed is to manipulate the dissemination of information. A focus on an isolated knower obscures the impact that industry has in shaping what information is available. To address these problems medical knowledge must be understood from a social epistemological framework. Finally, and most importantly, the arms race account suggests that the goal of identifying the perfect experimental design or inference pattern is chimerical. There is no final resolution to the fundamental antagonism between commercial and scientific forces. There is only a next move.
Tam, Man-yee County, et 譚敏義. « The interiorization of life nuturing skills and the medical culture in late imperial China ». Thesis, The University of Hong Kong (Pokfulam, Hong Kong), 2009. http://hub.hku.hk/bib/B43085817.
Texte intégralNicolae, Daniel Sebastian. « A mediaeval court physician at work : Ibn Jumay''s commentary on the Canon of Medicine ». Thesis, University of Oxford, 2012. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:e8e53786-7e15-4cf9-928b-dd492a740acd.
Texte intégralLivres sur le sujet "Medicine – Philosophy – History"
Writings on medicine. New York : Fordham University Press, 2012.
Trouver le texte intégralGreek rational medicine : Philosophy and medicine from Alcmaeon to the Alexandrians. London : Routledge, 1993.
Trouver le texte intégralNewsome, Frederick V. An African American philosophy of medicine. Pittsburgh, PA : Dorrance Publishing Co, 2020.
Trouver le texte intégralCanguilhem, Georges. Writings on medicine. New York : Fordham University Press, 2012.
Trouver le texte intégralShelton, Herbert M. The myth of medicine. Boca Raton, FL : Cool Hand Communications, 1995.
Trouver le texte intégralDisease : In search of remedy. Urbana : University of Illinois Press, 1996.
Trouver le texte intégralS, Rousseau G., Gill Miranda et Haycock David Boyd 1968-, dir. Framing and imagining disease in cultural history. Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire : Palgrave Macmillan, 2003.
Trouver le texte intégral1948-, Löwy Ilana, dir. The Polish school of philosophy of medicine : From Tytus Chalubinski (1820-1889) to Ludwik Fleck (1896-1961). Dordrecht : Kluwer Academic, 1990.
Trouver le texte intégralU, Unschuld Paul. Chinese medicine. Brookline, Mass : Paradign Publications, 1998.
Trouver le texte intégralMauskopf, Seymour. Integrating History and Philosophy of Science : Problems and Prospects. Dordrecht : Springer Science+Business Media B.V., 2011.
Trouver le texte intégralChapitres de livres sur le sujet "Medicine – Philosophy – History"
Reed, James. « History of Contraceptive Practices ». Dans Philosophy and Medicine, 15–38. Dordrecht : Springer Netherlands, 1987. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-3397-2_2.
Texte intégralNoonan, John T. « The History of Contraception : Seven Choices ». Dans Philosophy and Medicine, 3–14. Dordrecht : Springer Netherlands, 1987. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-3397-2_1.
Texte intégralPeset, José Luis. « On the History of Medical Causality ». Dans Philosophy and Medicine, 57–74. Dordrecht : Springer Netherlands, 1993. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2960-4_5.
Texte intégralGardell, Mary Ann. « Sexual Ethics : Some Perspectives from the History of Philosophy ». Dans Philosophy and Medicine, 3–15. Dordrecht : Springer Netherlands, 1987. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-3943-2_1.
Texte intégralSobiech, Frank. « Niels Stensen’s Character Sketch in History (Seventeenth to Twenty-First Century) ». Dans Philosophy and Medicine, 155–83. Cham : Springer International Publishing, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-32912-3_3.
Texte intégralMcCullough, Laurence B. « The Place of Percival’s Medical Ethics in the History of Medical Ethics ». Dans Philosophy and Medicine, 239–88. Cham : Springer International Publishing, 2022. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-86036-3_4.
Texte intégralBoorse, Christopher. « Goals of Medicine ». Dans History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, 145–77. Cham : Springer International Publishing, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-29091-1_9.
Texte intégralMcCullough, Laurence B. « Thomas Percival Joins Gregory’s Moral Revolution Against the Long Tradition of Entrepreneurial Medicine in the History of Western Medicine ». Dans Philosophy and Medicine, 149–237. Cham : Springer International Publishing, 2022. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-86036-3_3.
Texte intégralAnstey, Peter R. « John Locke and Helmontian Medicine ». Dans Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 93–117. Dordrecht : Springer Netherlands, 2010. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3686-5_6.
Texte intégralKeane, Niall. « On the Origins of Illness and the Hiddenness of Health : A Hermeneutic Approach to the History of a Problem ». Dans Philosophy and Medicine, 57–72. Dordrecht : Springer Netherlands, 2015. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9870-9_4.
Texte intégralActes de conférences sur le sujet "Medicine – Philosophy – History"
MARTSENIUK, Maryna. « ON THE INFLUENCE OF HAPPINESS ON HUMAN HEALTH ». Dans Happiness And Contemporary Society : Conference Proceedings Volume. SPOLOM, 2021. http://dx.doi.org/10.31108/7.2021.42.
Texte intégralCanina, Marita. « Biodesign : Overcoming Disciplinary Barriers ». Dans ASME 2008 9th Biennial Conference on Engineering Systems Design and Analysis. ASMEDC, 2008. http://dx.doi.org/10.1115/esda2008-59458.
Texte intégralRapports d'organisations sur le sujet "Medicine – Philosophy – History"
Maksimenko, L. A., et G. V. Gornova. Candidate's exam in the discipline "History and philosophy of science" : a textbook for organizing independent educational and research work on an abstract on the history of medicine. OFERNIO, novembre 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.12731/ofernio.2020.24680.
Texte intégral