Littérature scientifique sur le sujet « Dragmaticon »

Créez une référence correcte selon les styles APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard et plusieurs autres

Choisissez une source :

Consultez les listes thématiques d’articles de revues, de livres, de thèses, de rapports de conférences et d’autres sources académiques sur le sujet « Dragmaticon ».

À côté de chaque source dans la liste de références il y a un bouton « Ajouter à la bibliographie ». Cliquez sur ce bouton, et nous générerons automatiquement la référence bibliographique pour la source choisie selon votre style de citation préféré : APA, MLA, Harvard, Vancouver, Chicago, etc.

Vous pouvez aussi télécharger le texte intégral de la publication scolaire au format pdf et consulter son résumé en ligne lorsque ces informations sont inclues dans les métadonnées.

Articles de revues sur le sujet "Dragmaticon"

1

Roccati, G. Matteo. « Guillaume de Conches, Philosophia & ; Dragmaticon ». Studi Francesi, no 198 (LXVI | III) (1 décembre 2022) : 668. http://dx.doi.org/10.4000/studifrancesi.50866.

Texte intégral
Styles APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, etc.
2

Brannon, James. « Bi-Daily Venus in the Medieval Thought of William of Conches : Explaining an Uncommon Celestial Event by Circumsolarity ». Journal for the History of Astronomy 51, no 3 (août 2020) : 305–23. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0021828620932701.

Texte intégral
Résumé :
Bi-Daily Venus (BDV) is an uncommon event, occurring when an observer can view that planet twice in a single day – in the twilight of dawn and dusk. That William of Conches knew of this phenomenon in twelfth-century France is surprising given the dearth of BDV accounts. Yet following unnamed sources, he discussed BDV in three of his works: Philosophia Mundi, Glosae Super Boetium, and Dragmaticon. From the appearance of the first of these volumes (ca. 1125) to the last (ca. 1145), William’s reasoning for BDV’s occurrence changed from mild scepticism of given explanations to acceptance of Venus’s sometimes circumsolar height above the sun as the correct interpretation. This paper examines William’s evolving BDV discussions, considers what planetary height meant to William, presents an explanatory diagram, and concludes that William understood Venus to be within the ecliptic plane when BDV occurs – in contrast to our modern explanation for BDV.
Styles APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, etc.
3

Lanzieri Júnior, Carlile. « As histórias de um livro catedral : relações entre passado, presente e futuro na interpretação do Dragmaticon do mestre Guilherme de Conches (1080-1154) ». Revista Veredas da História 11, no 1 (4 août 2018). http://dx.doi.org/10.9771/rvh.v11i1.47897.

Texte intégral
Résumé :
Escrito entre os anos de 1144 e 1149, o Dragmaticon divide-se em seis livros que trazem muitas das concepções pedagógicas de Guilherme de Conches (1090-1154). Concepções assinaladas por uma percepção profunda do tempo, o que nos sugere a intensa relação que Guilherme estabeleceu entre experiências passadas e expectativas futuras diante de um presente que considerava decadente e que teria pouco a ensinar aos que a ele se inclinavam. Ombro a ombro com personagens como João de Salisbury (c.1120-1180), Bernardo de Chartres (†1160) e Gilberto de La Porrée (1076-1154), Guilherme de Conches atuou na consolidação do que foi denominado pela posteridade como a Escola da Catedral de Chartres, uma das importantes expressões da cultura intelectual do século XII.
Styles APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, etc.

Thèses sur le sujet "Dragmaticon"

1

Ferrara, Carmine. « Guglielmo di Conches e il Dragmaticon philosophiae ». Doctoral thesis, Universita degli studi di Salerno, 2016. http://hdl.handle.net/10556/2336.

Texte intégral
Résumé :
2013 - 2014
This dissertation about William of Conches and the Dragmaticon Philosophiae is divided into two sections. The aim of the first section is to reconstruct the life and the literary works of one of the most important teachers of Chartres of the twelfth century. The aim of the second section is to analyse his most important work, written between 1146 and 1149, after undergoing a noteworthy process of rethinking, reorganization and enlargement of his youthful work, called Philosophia, which had been bitterly attacked by the cistercian monk William of Saint-Thierry, who denounced its serious theological errors in 1140 or 1141. The enquiry about the life of William of Conches, to which the first chapter is dedicated, has produced some interesting results, which seem to open new areas of research, especially regarding the philosopher’s place of birth (which may not well be Conches, but Saint-Martin du Tilleul) and the last phase of his life, which could have ended in England at the court of Henry II (to whom William was tutor during the writing of the Dragmaticon), or in Paris as magister scholae. The enquiry about the literary works of William of Conches, to which the second chapter is dedicated, deals with a detailed presentation of the historiographical debate, that has so far led to the identification of the works currently attributed to the philosopher. The first part of the third chapter is devoted to the analysis of the accusations, with which William of Saint-Thierry attacked the teacher of Chartres in his De erroribus Guillelmi de Conchis, and to the verification of their legitimacy. The second part instead is dedicated to the description of the Dragmaticon’ structure and the novelties of this work with respect to Philosophia, the presentation of the Dragmaticon’ s purpose, thus the tractatus de substantiis, and the description of the research method used. With respect to the latter, William of Conches claims to conduct his research philosophice, in accordance with the typical approach of philosophers, who deal with universals expressing themselves through rationes necessariae, but when he investigates the substances of the physical world, he cannot always argue philosophice about them because of their mutability, and must sometimes argue dialectice, in accordance with the typical approach of dialecticians, who deal with particulars expressing themselves through rationes verisimiles. 2 The fourth chapter is devoted to the presentation of William’s definition of substance as res per se existens and to the description of the species of substance in the order in which William presents them in the Dragmaticon. After he speaks about God and the angels expressing himself through rationes necessariae derived from faith, he then deals with the elements. In the Dragmaticon William defines element as what is first in the composition and last in the resolution of the body and describes it as a body that is invisible, imperceptible and unextended per se. The feature of unextention attribuited to elementary bodies gives them a paradoxical ontological status, as there are no bodies devoid of the three dimensions of space. But the paradoxicalness of this description stems from the fact that in the Dragmaticon William describes element from the point of view of philosophers, who speak about universals expressing themselves through rationes necessariae. According to philosophers element is a body without dimension, because it is not a physical being, but a metaphyisical one, that is an abstract form similar to a geometric point. The philosopher then can only postulate the existence of beings, which are first in the composition and last in the resolution of the body, but he cannot prove their existence in re. However, it is from the fact that postulating the existence of simple and minimal particles of the bodies is more rational than not postulating it, that can stem the existence in re of these particles. The fifth chapter is devoted to the distinction between opus creatoris and opus naturae. God creates simultaneously all elements ex nichilo, mixed in a big body mass, so as to occupy all the existent room. The following exornatio mundi, which is the correct and balanced disposition of the elements in the world and the formation of the bodies of living creatures, concerns nature, a kind of ordering principle inside the elements, which God uses to produce the same from the same in the world. In the exornatio mundi nature operates within the concept of the same from the same, when it drives the elements to their cosmic place. In an already formed world nature operates the same from the same, when it initiates physiological mechanisms (like generation and formation of bodies, nutrition, appetition, ritention, digestion, expulsion, growth and sleep) typical of an organic structure. The sixth chapter deals with the description of the works of nature in the world through the analysis of the main macrocosmic phenomena, which take place in the four elementa mundi. The seventh chapter is devoted to the description of the operations in the human body which depend on nature, and of those that do not depend on nature, but on the soul. 3 Some of the operations that depend on the soul (like breathing, sense, imagination and voluntary motion) are common to animals and men. Some others (like wit, memory, opinion, reason and intelligence) are common to men and divine spirits. The animal soul is mortal and develops spontaneously in an organic body, whereas the human soul is a separate and immortal substance. It’s created directly by God and joins the body without changing its physical nature and takes its course by means of a very fine airy substance, that arises from the liver, goes through the heart, where it causes breath, and arrives in the brain after two refining phases. [edited by Author]
XIII n.s.
Styles APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, etc.

Livres sur le sujet "Dragmaticon"

1

Occidentalium, Centre Traditio Litterarum, dir. Guillelmus de Conchis Dragmaticon philosophiae. Turnhout : Brepols, 2001.

Trouver le texte intégral
Styles APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, etc.
2

William. Guillelmi de Conchis dragmaticon philosophiae. Turnholti : Brepols, 1997.

Trouver le texte intégral
Styles APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, etc.
3

William. A dialogue on natural philosophy = : Dragmaticon philosophiae. Notre Dame, Ind : University of Notre Dame Press, 1997.

Trouver le texte intégral
Styles APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, etc.
4

Dussourt, Christiane, Bernard Ribemont et Emilia Ndiaye. Philosophia et Dragmaticon. Societe d'edition Les Belles lettres, 2021.

Trouver le texte intégral
Styles APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, etc.
5

Curr, Matthew, et William. William of Conches : A Dialogue on Natural Philosophy (Dragmaticon Philosophiae) (Notre Dame Texts in Medieval Culture, V. 2). University of Notre Dame Press, 1998.

Trouver le texte intégral
Styles APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, etc.

Chapitres de livres sur le sujet "Dragmaticon"

1

« 3 Visuelle Darbietungen in Wilhelms von Conches Dragmaticon philosophiae ». Dans Visuelle Weltaneignung, 93–182. Göttingen : Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2008. http://dx.doi.org/10.13109/9783666367113.93.

Texte intégral
Styles APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, etc.
2

« The influence of the Pantegni on William of Conches’s Dragmaticon ». Dans Constantine the African and ‘Alī Ibn al-‘Abbās al-Mağūsī, 266–85. BRILL, 1994. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/9789004377356_014.

Texte intégral
Styles APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, etc.
3

« William of Conches, Dragmaticon, Bk 6, Ch. 22 on smell (1147–1149) ». Dans The Medieval Natural World, 159. Routledge, 2013. http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9781315833316-37.

Texte intégral
Styles APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, etc.
Nous offrons des réductions sur tous les plans premium pour les auteurs dont les œuvres sont incluses dans des sélections littéraires thématiques. Contactez-nous pour obtenir un code promo unique!

Vers la bibliographie