Tesis sobre el tema "Contrarietà"
Crea una cita precisa en los estilos APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard y otros
Consulte los 26 mejores tesis para su investigación sobre el tema "Contrarietà".
Junto a cada fuente en la lista de referencias hay un botón "Agregar a la bibliografía". Pulsa este botón, y generaremos automáticamente la referencia bibliográfica para la obra elegida en el estilo de cita que necesites: APA, MLA, Harvard, Vancouver, Chicago, etc.
También puede descargar el texto completo de la publicación académica en formato pdf y leer en línea su resumen siempre que esté disponible en los metadatos.
Explore tesis sobre una amplia variedad de disciplinas y organice su bibliografía correctamente.
Turatto, Silvia <1979>. "L'impugnazione del lodo rituale per contrarietà all'ordine pubblico". Doctoral thesis, Alma Mater Studiorum - Università di Bologna, 2011. http://amsdottorato.unibo.it/4118/1/turatto_silvia_tesi.pdf.
Texto completoTuratto, Silvia <1979>. "L'impugnazione del lodo rituale per contrarietà all'ordine pubblico". Doctoral thesis, Alma Mater Studiorum - Università di Bologna, 2011. http://amsdottorato.unibo.it/4118/.
Texto completoCariou, Warren. "Mixed media, intention and contrariety in Blake's art". Thesis, National Library of Canada = Bibliothèque nationale du Canada, 1998. http://www.collectionscanada.ca/obj/s4/f2/dsk2/tape15/PQDD_0015/NQ35121.pdf.
Texto completoAnfindsen, Jens Tomas. "Aristotle on contrariety as a principle of first philosophy /". Uppsala : Department of Philosophy, Uppsala University, 2006. http://urn.kb.se/resolve?urn=urn:nbn:se:uu:diva-6848.
Texto completoPlant, John. "Heyoka : Die Contraries und Clowns der Plainsindianer /". Wyk (Allemagne) : Verlag für Amerikanistik, 1994. http://catalogue.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/cb37461045g.
Texto completoSteczowicz, Agnieszka. "'The defence of contraries' : paradox in the late Renaissance disciplnes". Thesis, University of Oxford, 2004. https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:f2f93089-60f6-4408-aae9-2b3e595efcdc.
Texto completoDE, MADDALENA LINDA. "LITIS CAUSA MALO MORE PECUNIAM PROMITTERE: SULLA CONTRARIETA' AI BONI MORES DEL 'PATTO DI QUOTA LITE'". Doctoral thesis, Università degli Studi di Milano, 2015. http://hdl.handle.net/2434/254199.
Texto completoDie Vereinbarung, welche gegenwärtig in der Rechtspraxis als quota-litis-Vereinbarung bekannt ist, hat ihre Wurzeln im römischen Recht. Bei dieser Vereinbarung übernimmt der Rechtsanwalt die Vertretung des Mandanten mit der Absprache, dass jener als Honorar einen Teil von dem erhalten soll, was dieser im Fall eines Prozessgewinns erlangen wird. Das Institut der quota-litis-Vereinbarung ist häufig Gegenstand strenger Verbote. Beispiele einer solchen Reaktion der Rechtsordnung findet man – wenn auch mit verschiedenen Abstufungen – im schweizerischen wie auch im italienischen Recht. Einerseits war die quota-litis-Vereinbarung in der Schweizer Eidgenossenschaft sowohl auf kantonaler als auch auf föderaler Ebene schon seit jeher verboten, um das öffentliche Interesse daran zu schützen, dass der Berufsträger in seinen Entscheidungen unabhängig ist, wenn er eine Rechtssache führt, und sich nicht von persönlichen Interessen leiten lässt, die auf irgendeine Art seine Neutralität gefährden können. Andererseits erfuhr sie in Italien verschiedene Reformen, die zwar bisweilen eine Teilöffnung der Rechtsordnung mit sich brachten, aber stets an dem Prinzip ihrer Widerrechtlichkeit festhielten; wie sich aus der höchstrichterlichen Rechtsprechung ergibt, verfolgt man damit den Zweck zu vermeiden, dass der Rechtsanwalt seinen Einfluss missbraucht, um den Großteil der streitgegenständlichen Sache zu beanspruchen, und infolgedessen keine Position der Unparteilichkeit und Unabhängigkeit im Hinblick auf den Rechtsstreit gewährleistet, an dem er mitwirkt. Nach diesem anfänglichen rechtsvergleichenden Exkurs werden mit Hilfe der exegetischen Methode diejenigen römischen Quellenzeugnisse untersucht, welche höchstwahrscheinlich diese rechtswidrige Vereinbarung betreffen. Eine skeptische Haltung ist zwingend erforderlich, da die Urheberschaft des Ausdrucks pactum de quota litis, anders als in der juristischen Literatur aller Epochen immer behauptet wird, nicht den Römern selbst zuzuerkennen ist, sondern ihren mittelalterlichen Exegeten, den Glossatoren und den Kommentatoren, die als erste den Ausdruck geprägt haben, den wir heute kennen. Es handelt sich hauptsächlich um klassische und spätantike Rechtsquellen, insbesondere um zwei responsa des Juristen Ulpian (D. 50, 13, 1, 12; D. 2, 14, 53), um einen Ausschnitt aus der Institutio Oratoria des Rhetors Quintilian (Inst. 12, 7, 11) und um zwei constitutiones des Kaisers Konstantin (C. 2, 6, 5 und CTh. 2, 10, 4), in denen das missbilligende Empfinden aufscheint, welches eine solche Vereinbarung zwischen dem Anwalt (oder zuweilen auch zwischen dem procurator ad litem und dem dominus litis) und dem Klienten auslöste. Ihr Widerspruch zu den boni mores ergibt sich in den Texten aus Wendungen wie malo more, non licet, abominanda negotiato und illecita compendia. Allerdings geht aus diesen nicht die ratio dieses Widerspruchs zu den guten Sitten hervor. Auf diese Frage wurde versucht, eine Antwort zu geben, indem auf die sozialen und wirtschaftlichen Beweggründe verwiesen wurde, welche den Übergang von der Unabdingbarkeit des Prinzips der Unentgeltlichkeit der Anwaltstätigkeit zu der Festlegung gesetzlich bestimmter Honorare kennzeichneten, die auch durch kaiserliche Reskripte bezeugt sind. Es konnte jedoch nicht von der Vertiefung einer weiteren Frage abgesehen werden, deren enger Zusammenhang und deren gleichzeitige Komplexität in den Lehrmeinungen deutlich wurde, die an dieser Stelle untersucht und überprüft wurden. Ich beziehe mich auf das Institut der redemptio litis, welches gemäß der allgemeinen Überzeugung der Gelehrten des 16. und 17. Jahrhunderts (z. B. Johann Schilter, Johann Brunnemann, Iacobus Curtius) mit dem Fall einer quota-litis-Vereinbarung völlig vergleichbar war. Es wurde versucht, hierzu Stellung zu nehmen, indem der Literatur des vergangenen Jahrhunderts zu diesem Thema zugestimmt wurde (z. B. Vittorio Scialoja und jüngst Mariano Scarlato-Fazio und Gianni Santucci), gemäß der es sich um zwei Tatbstände handeln soll, die zwar gleichermaßen unrechtmäßig gewesen seien, sich aber dem Inhalt nach unterschieden hätten. Redimere litem bedeutet in den Quellen für gewöhnlich “das Prozessrisiko übernehmen” gegen Zahlung eines Entgelts (so in D. 17, 1, 6, 7; D. 17, 1, 7; C. 2, 12, 15; C. 4, 35, 20), indem man auf den Mechanismus der Prozessübernahme zurückgreift, der die Übertragung von Forderungen und Schulden auf den procurator in rem suam gestattete; dieser Terminus erlangt auch die Bedeutung “kostengünstig eine Forderung erwerben”, um von dem Schuldner der abgetretenen Forderung ihren gesamten Nominalwert einzutreiben (so in C. 4, 35, 22, wo der Inhalt der lex Anastasiana berichtet wird). In beiden Fällen herrscht das spekulative Element vor und beide Tatbestände wurden von der Rechtsordnung nicht toleriert, da man sie als den guten Sitten zuwider beurteilte. Sicherlich konnte auch die redemptio litis ebenso wie die quota-litis-Vereinbarung, mit der sie die Sittenwidrigkeit gemein hatte, verwendet werden, um den Anwalt (oder den Prozessübernehmer) zu entlohnen; aber es handelte sich in jedem Fall um eine nach Art (Zession einer streitbefangenen Forderung und nicht einfach ein pactum) und Inhalt (Erwerb der ganzen prozessualen Lage des Zedenten und nicht eines Teils des Erlöses im Fall des Prozessgewinns) andere Vereinbarung. Die untrennbare Verbindung zwischen dem technischen Hilfsmittel, mit dem man die redemptio litis verwirklichte, der procuratio ad litem in rem suam, und dem Mandat bildete den Schwerpunkt der Ausarbeitung von abschließenden Erwägungen betreffend die Widerrechtlichkeit einer derartigen Vereinbarung im römischen Recht der Klassik und Spätklassik.
Stiker-Métral, Charles-Olivier. "Narcisse contrarié : l'amour propre dans le discours moral en France, 1650-1715 /". Paris : H. Champion, 2007. http://catalogue.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/cb41000255f.
Texto completoAupetit, Hubert. "La nécessité biblique : de l'Esprit géométrique aux Pensées de Pascal". Thesis, Lyon 2, 2015. http://www.theses.fr/2015LYO20131.
Texto completoA thorough philological study of l'Esprit géométrique shows an evolution in Pascal's epistemology. Discovering a form of natural corruption in the incapacity of self foundation of the human langage, he leaves his former Cartesian positions. As a consequence, Reason's pretention to formulate universal principles is erased : every rational knowledge is based on a form of authority. This reveals the importance of Pascal's scientific work as regards to the crisis of fundation in modern Science. Using Aristotle's Poetic's methods, I show that Augustinian notion of figuration both applies to mathematics and Biblic litterature, and gives the aesthetic unity of the whole Pascal’s work . Its originality in philosophy is to get rid of scepticism by searching new languages capable of certitude. I reopen a long debate on the unaccomplished Pensées. I propose to distinguish between objective and apologetic editions. The latter are based on some of the author's indications on his intentions, the former use the only classification available. The thorough originality of what I call Les Pensées classées is to propose a quest for happiness with no religious a priori. After having established the contrarieties of humain condition which no philosophy or human science can describe or resolve because they reject contradiction, as a principle, this classification introduces the Christian Scripture as it carries the only language capable of accepting contradiction and giving a meaning to it. There are two new approaches here : introducing the Bible in the field of existence by necessity, and as a simple book with cognitive power. Structured by narration and figuration (typology), this Biblical model extends rational knowledge by extending its restricted space-time referential. It enlarges the horizon of existence of the reader and shows a path for repairing their contrarieties. Pascal deeply renews the classic figurative thought and the poetic approach of the Bible
Flynn, John F. X. ""By Contraries" ("Ulysses" 15.3928): James Joyce's Rendering of Drama in "Exiles" and "Circe"". W&M ScholarWorks, 2000. https://scholarworks.wm.edu/etd/1539626257.
Texto completoDyc, Anna. "“Without contraries there is no progression”:The Paradoxical Heterogeneity of Identity in Sinead O’Connor’s Poetic Expression". Thesis, Högskolan Dalarna, Engelska, 2005. http://urn.kb.se/resolve?urn=urn:nbn:se:du-2084.
Texto completoBolduc, Michelle. "The poetics of contraries : the sacred and profane in vernacular literature of the High Middle Ages /". view abstract or download file of text, 2000. http://wwwlib.umi.com/cr/uoregon/fullcit?p9963442.
Texto completoTypescript. Includes vita and abstract. Includes bibliographical references (leaves 336-360). Also available for download via the World Wide Web; free to University of Oregon users. Address: http://wwwlib.umi.com/cr/uoregon/fullcit?p9963442.
Frobert, Ludovic. "L'économie de l'homme raisonnable une relecture du développement contrarié de l'hétérodoxie française du premier tiers du XXème siècle /". Grenoble : A.N.R.T. Université Pierre Mendès France Grenoble 2, 1994. http://bibpurl.oclc.org/web/34700.
Texto completoDebourg, Claire. "Les contrariétés de décisions dans l’arbitrage international". Thesis, Paris 10, 2011. http://www.theses.fr/2011PA100070.
Texto completoThe phenomenon of conflicting decisions is extremely hazardous. On the one hand, they represent a threat to the coherence of the legal systems. On the other hand, it places a burden on the parties, putting them in an inextricable situation. Being a jurisdictional dispute resolution method, international arbitration does not escape this phenomenon. On the contrary, the specificities of arbitration make it the territory of predilection for the appearance of conflicting decisions. In fact, conflicting decisions result from the conduction of parallel proceedings concerning identical issues, which receive a different analysis. International arbitration aggravates the classical causes resulting in conflicting decisions. These causes are the competition between jurisdictions and the incoherence of the solutions.The risk of the existence of conflicting decisions is frequent and it presents itself is several manners. It can oppose national courts’ decisions assisting and controlling the arbitration, an arbitral award and a national court’s decision or even two arbitral awards.Despite the gravity of the problem and the frequency of the risk of having conflicting decisions, international arbitration seems unarmed to deal with it. Firstly, it is confronted with the limited efficiency of the curative solutions, and secondly, with the difficulties of applying preventive solutions
Mercier, Franck Chiffoleau Jacques. "L'enfer du décor la Vauderie d'Arras (1459-1491) ou l'émergence contrariée d'une nouvelle souveraineté autour des ducs Valois de Bourgogne (XVe siècle) /". [S.l.] : [s.n.], 2001. http://demeter.univ-lyon2.fr:8080/sdx/theses/lyon2/2001/mercier_f.
Texto completoGava, Jean-François. "Disparate de l'opposition et de la contrarietas : d’une confusion vivace et de la productivité de sa dissipation pour une théorie non hégélienne de la transformation sociale". Toulouse 2, 2007. http://www.theses.fr/2007TOU20036.
Texto completoThrough this work, we have been trying to criticize the notion of opposition from a social transformation theory point of view. With this aim, we first attempted to review the various theories of opposition through modern philosophical history, and then disqualified them all but one, of which we showed the highest relevance for our purpose: spinozian contrarietas. Particularly we focused on hegelian essentialities within the ‘difference dialectics’ of his great logic of essence: opposition and dialectical contradiction. We confronted them with Kantian notions of Realopposition, Realentgegensetzung, etc. Summing up the discussion that Hegel himself has with Kant. It appears that the various expressions of Kantian ‘real opposition’ are just the dynamized version of dialectical opposition. Our starting point was, together with a already existing discussion by L. Colletti of the contrast between real opposition and contradiction, the reminiscence of the marxian 1843 manuscript of Kreuznach, namely the Kritik des hegelschen Staatsrecht. There indeed can be found the famous paradoxical expresssion of ‘really opposed extremities’, which do not appeal to each other, nor do they attract or repel each other, because their essences are opposed – entgegengesezt: State versus civil society. Even if the mentioned text remained unpublished during the author's life, it seemed to us that this paradox was worth being retrieved, for it expresses the break of the State-society dialectics. Although this break never was theorized as such by Marx, it means to us the end of a certain recapitulative ratio oriented toward domination, and the renewed passage to a spinozian culture of oblivion as a method of social transformation
Kim, Eunju. "La causalité imaginaire chez Spinoza". Thesis, Lyon, École normale supérieure, 2012. http://www.theses.fr/2012ENSL0726.
Texto completoThe notion of cause is the alpha and omega of Ethics. But it appears mostly in an oblique way: through "the idea of an external cause" that accompanies the derived passions. The cause, imagined assignable, is actually no more assignable. As the individual is complex, it is difficult to disentangle what is happening in it from the exterior, from what is produced by the interior. In passion, one is modified unwittingly to become a subject of what happens to him, and understand the cause of this change under the form of a story. This imaginary dynamics, I call it "imaginary causality" and explain it in mechanical terms. I establish first the key features of Spinoza’s mechanics: the ontological positivity of each idea (acting nature); the multiplicity of referential frames that intersect at a single nature (envelopment); and the concept of the individual as originally composed (nesting individuals). The coexistence of these referential frames around only one of them, this is precisely what constitutes the structure of imaginary causality, and the variation of their proportion, its actual content. In accordance with this structure, I apply "conatus", self-preservation principle, to ideas or affects at first, to show that desire, actual essence of a man, is a complex of affects which, as individuals themselves, mediate the influence of others. It turns out that imaginary causality is the very mechanical causality, concerning the complex individuals. Finally, while I refer to Freudian psychic causality, I attempt to outline a new concept of the unconscious: as relation without a subject or structure without a center
Traylen, Maryanne. "'Sol' and 'Luna', 'Burn in water and wash in fire'; some instances of contraries at work in Blake's 'Four Zoas', 'Milton' and 'Jerusalem' in light of Jung's thought and his alchemical undestanding in 'Mysterium coniunctionis'". Thesis, Swansea University, 1990. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.411169.
Texto completoYouansamouth, Edward. "'Two congenial beings of another sphere' : Peter Sterry as a theological precursor to William Blake". Thesis, University of Oxford, 2018. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:4e5b37ea-be6c-4397-8ebc-aeb6dde63d82.
Texto completoWittmann, Valérie. "Les interférences entre instances civiles et pénales parallèles : contribution à l'étude de la cohérence en matière juridictionnelle". Thesis, Dijon, 2011. http://www.theses.fr/2011DIJOD002.
Texto completoAWhen civil and penal proceedings occur in parallel, there is a risk of conflicting judgments, which positive law traditionally precludes by making penal proceedings paramount and by deferring adjudication on article 4 of the Criminal Code. This double mechanism, which ensures supremacy of criminal proceedings over civil proceedings, is quite singular. Indeed, it guarantees that the justifications for the decisions made are coherent. In other contentious matters, positive law pays little attention to such concerns. Moreover, it is unilateral, since it exclusively favours criminal law decisions. Though this supremacy was initially justified by the notion that criminal law decisions guaranteed truth, analysis has shown that this is largely debatable. First of all, with regard to the foundations themselves, this mechanism of course ensures a certain coherence of the matters judged, but maintains an appearance of truth rather than a guarantee of truth. Yet, precisely, the coherence of the justifications for distinct judgments is only legitimate insofar as it seeks to determine the truth. Then with regard to the system itself, the supremacy of criminal over civil proceedings interferes with the freedom of the civil judge, and violates by its absolute nature, the adversarial principle, while the systematic deferral of adjudication slows down procedures and undermines the objective of celerity. In order to remedy these drawbacks, legislators and jurisprudence have made an effort to limit the most damaging effects of this principle, by dissociating civil from repressive concepts, then by compartmentalising each within strict limits. Nevertheless, the objective of celerity finally won the day and legislators, through the law of 5th March 2007, retained the compulsory nature of the deferral of adjudication of article 4, but only with regard to civil action for damages resulting from the offence. The new law now establishes the principle of independence of parallel proceedings, even though it carries a risk of conflicting results. For the time being, however, the jurisdictions take into account the risk of conflicting results and have maintained the supremacy of criminal proceedings over civil proceedings. It is nonetheless desirable to revise the recent law, and to incorporate in the reasons which are necessary support for the criminal decision, the value of a refragable presumption of truth. The specific nature of decisions in criminal proceedings would thus be taken into account, and the sometimes antagonistic requirement of autonomy of the different jurisdictions, the coherence of the matters being judged, and the search for truth would thus be preserved
Pisani, Federico. "Knowledge workers management. Concorrenza e invenzioni nel rapporto di lavoro subordinato: il modello statunitense". Doctoral thesis, Università degli studi di Padova, 2019. http://hdl.handle.net/11577/3425914.
Texto completoThis work addresses the issues of competition and inventions in the U.S. employment relationships. The research was carried out in part at the Boston University School of Law of, under the supervision of Micheal C. Harper, professor of Labour Law. The selection of the topic is justified in the light of its importance, given that in the new production organization, based largely on globalized knowledge, employees are now increasingly being asked for professionalism, innovation and creativity. The decision to examine this issue from the perspective of the "U.S. laboratory" is due to the primacy that this nation holds at international level on the economic, scientific and innovation of work processes, which bring out critical issues that in other Countries probably have not yet been raised. In order to frame the above-mentioned topics, it has become appropriate to give an account of the system of regulatory sources in the USA, with particular focus on the Restatement of Employment Law, i.e. the collection of fundamental principles developed over the years by common law in the field of employment relationships. The examination of the sources is followed by the definition of the concept of employee and self-employed worker (independent contractor), necessary for the assessment of the application of the obligations arising from the employment relationships, including the duty of loyalty, involved in the fiduciary law. In this context, the evolution of the case law has been observed, as well as the examination of the criteria relating to the distinction between employees and independent contractors, mainly concerning the judgement on the relevance of the factual elements determining the assessment of the existence of an employment relationship. Subsequently, this study addresses the issue of the typical form of the U.S. employment contract, the so-called employment-at-will. This peculiarity is originated from the principle that the parties are not bound by any obligation to provide reasons for termination. The third part of the work has as its object the discipline of competition of the worker carried out on the basis of the knowledge acquired, legally or illegally, during the relationship and the relative legal remedies for the employer, against the violation of the duty of loyalty, intended as an obligation of the employee to perform the work in the exclusive interest of the entrepreneur and, consequently, to refrain from engaging in prejudicial conduct against the company. About the remedies available in the event of breach of the obligations examined, the legal and equitable remedies that U.S. law offers the employer have been explained. The final part of this study deals with the rules governing the ownership of rights arising from inventions developed by employees in the course of their employment. The definitions of "invention" and "patent" and their relationship in the context of employment law has been examined and the difference between invention as a work of genius and intellectual property protected by copyright has been highlighted. In addition, the mechanisms underlying the basic rules governing the subject matter and their coexistence with the contractual freedom of the parties and their power to dispose of these rights have been observed.
Fitzwilliams, Catherine Carr. "A unity of contraries Dorothy Day and the 'no-alibi' rhetoric of defiance and devotion /". 2009. http://digital.library.duq.edu/u?/etd,111222.
Texto completoWuchner, Emily Michelle. "AN INTRICATE SIMPLICITY: CONTRARIES AS AN EVOCATION OF THE SUBLIME IN MOZART’S JUPITER SYMPHONY, K. 551". 2011. http://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_gradthes/925.
Texto completoBurman, Thomas E. "Spain's Arab Christian and Islam, c. 1050-1200 the text of the Liber denudationis (alias Contrarietas alfolica) and its intellectual milieu /". 1991. http://catalog.hathitrust.org/api/volumes/oclc/27972567.html.
Texto completoIncludes abstract. eContent provider-neutral record in process. Description based on print version record. Includes bibliographical references (leaves [348]-357).
Kasting, Gretchen Marie. "Without contraries there is no progression : scientific speculation and absence in Frankenstein, Strange case of Dr Jekyll and Mr Hyde, and “The colour out of space”". 2013. http://hdl.handle.net/2152/22740.
Texto completotext
Bader, Daniel. "Platonic Craft and Medical Ethics". Thesis, 2010. http://hdl.handle.net/1807/26127.
Texto completo