Journal articles on the topic 'The absoluteness of simultaneity'

To see the other types of publications on this topic, follow the link: The absoluteness of simultaneity.

Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles

Select a source type:

Consult the top 50 journal articles for your research on the topic 'The absoluteness of simultaneity.'

Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.

You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.

Browse journal articles on a wide variety of disciplines and organise your bibliography correctly.

1

Bagaria, Joan, and Sy D. Friedman. "Generic absoluteness." Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 108, no. 1-3 (March 2001): 3–13. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/s0168-0072(00)00038-5.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Habart, Karol. "On Absoluteness." Zeitschrift für Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 35, no. 5 (1989): 469–80. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/malq.19890350513.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Jongeneel, J. A. B. "De waarheid, absoluutheid en eigenheid van het christendom volgens Nederlandse protestanten." Theologia Reformata 62, no. 1 (March 1, 2019): 46–62. http://dx.doi.org/10.21827/5c5c4bbf4f7fd.

Full text
Abstract:
This article describes and analyses the views of 20th Dutch Protestant scholars of religious studies, systematic theology and missiology on ‘the absoluteness of Christianity/the revelation of God in Jesus Christ’, and their response to Western relativism rooted in the Enlightenment. Previous adherence to the Augustinian concept of Christianity as ‘the true religion,’ was exchanged for new ideas and positions that took them back to the essentials behind the concept of ‘the absoluteness of Christianity;’ to rethinking ‘absoluteness;’ ‘the non-absoluteness of Christianity;’ and alternative terms such as ‘finality,’ ‘originality,’ and ‘normativity.’ The concept of ‘the absoluteness of Christianity’ may have disappeared but elements thereof survive in new forms.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Spurk, Jan. "Simultaneity Within Non-Simultaneity?" Time & Society 13, no. 1 (March 2004): 41–49. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0961463x04040745.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Friedman, Sy D. "Generic Σ31 absoluteness." Journal of Symbolic Logic 69, no. 1 (March 2004): 73–80. http://dx.doi.org/10.2178/jsl/1080938826.

Full text
Abstract:
In this article we study the strength of absoluteness (with real parameters) in various types of generic extensions, correcting and improving some results from [3]. (In particular, see Theorem 3 below.) We shall also make some comments relating this work to the bounded forcing axioms BMM, BPFA and BSPFA.The statement “ absoluteness holds for ccc forcing” means that if a formula with real parameters has a solution in a ccc set-forcing extension of the universe V, then it already has a solution in V. The analogous definition applies when ccc is replaced by other set-forcing notions, or by class-forcing.Theorem 1. [1] absoluteness for ccc has no strength; i.e., if ZFC is consistent then so is ZFC + absoluteness for ccc.The following results concerning (arbitrary) set-forcing and class-forcing can be found in [3].Theorem 2 (Feng-Magidor-Woodin). (a) absoluteness for arbitrary set-forcing is equiconsistent with the existence of a reflecting cardinal, i.e., a regular cardinal κ such that H(κ) is ∑2-elementary in V.(b) absoluteness for class-forcing is inconsistent.We consider next the following set-forcing notions, which lie strictly between ccc and arbitrary set-forcing: proper, semiproper, stationary-preserving and ω1-preserving. We refer the reader to [8] for the definitions of these forcing notions.Using a variant of an argument due to Goldstern-Shelah (see [6]), we show the following. This result corrects Theorem 2 of [3] (whose proof only shows that if absoluteness holds in a certain proper forcing extension, then in L either ω1 is Mahlo or ω2 is inaccessible).
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Audrito, Giorgio, and Matteo Viale. "Absoluteness via resurrection." Journal of Mathematical Logic 17, no. 02 (November 27, 2017): 1750005. http://dx.doi.org/10.1142/s0219061317500052.

Full text
Abstract:
The resurrection axioms are forcing axioms introduced recently by Hamkins and Johnstone, developing on ideas of Chalons and Veličković. We introduce a stronger form of resurrection axioms (the iterated resurrection axioms [Formula: see text] for a class of forcings [Formula: see text] and a given ordinal [Formula: see text]), and show that [Formula: see text] implies generic absoluteness for the first-order theory of [Formula: see text] with respect to forcings in [Formula: see text] preserving the axiom, where [Formula: see text] is a cardinal which depends on [Formula: see text] ([Formula: see text] if [Formula: see text] is any among the classes of countably closed, proper, semiproper, stationary set preserving forcings). We also prove that the consistency strength of these axioms is below that of a Mahlo cardinal for most forcing classes, and below that of a stationary limit of supercompact cardinals for the class of stationary set preserving posets. Moreover, we outline that simultaneous generic absoluteness for [Formula: see text] with respect to [Formula: see text] and for [Formula: see text] with respect to [Formula: see text] with [Formula: see text] is in principle possible, and we present several natural models of the Morse–Kelley set theory where this phenomenon occurs (even for all [Formula: see text] simultaneously). Finally, we compare the iterated resurrection axioms (and the generic absoluteness results we can draw from them) with a variety of other forcing axioms, and also with the generic absoluteness results by Woodin and the second author.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Theisen, Bianca. "Simultaneity." MLN 121, no. 3 (2006): 514–21. http://dx.doi.org/10.1353/mln.2006.0078.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Koellner, Peter. "Strong Logics of First and Second Order." Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16, no. 1 (March 2010): 1–36. http://dx.doi.org/10.2178/bsl/1264433796.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractIn this paper we investigate strong logics of first and second order that have certain absoluteness properties. We begin with an investigation of first order logic and the strong logics ω-logic and β-logic, isolating two facets of absoluteness, namely, generic invariance and faithfulness. It turns out that absoluteness is relative in the sense that stronger background assumptions secure greater degrees of absoluteness. Our aim is to investigate the hierarchies of strong logics of first and second order that are generically invariant and faithful against the backdrop of the strongest large cardinal hypotheses. We show that there is a close correspondence between the two hierarchies and we characterize the strongest logic in each hierarchy. On the first-order side, this leads to a new presentation of Woodin's Ω-logic. On the second-order side, we compare the strongest logic with full second-order logic and argue that the comparison lends support to Quine's claim that second-order logic is really set theory in sheep's clothing.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Mejía, Diego Alejandro, and Ismael E. Rivera-Madrid. "Absoluteness theorems for arbitrary Polish spaces." Revista Colombiana de Matemáticas 53, no. 2 (July 1, 2019): 109–23. http://dx.doi.org/10.15446/recolma.v53n2.85521.

Full text
Abstract:
By coding Polish metric spaces with metrics on countable sets, we propose an interpretation of Polish metric spaces in models of ZFC and extend Mostowski's classical theorem of absoluteness of analytic sets for any Polish metric space in general. In addition, we prove a general version of Shoenfield's absoluteness theorem.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Cataldo, Carmine. "On the Absoluteness of Time." Applied Physics Research 9, no. 3 (May 31, 2017): 46. http://dx.doi.org/10.5539/apr.v9n3p46.

Full text
Abstract:
This paper aims to qualitatively summarize the results up until now obtained in investigating the compatibility between the absoluteness of time and several well-known phenomena, such as the alleged increase of the mean lifetime of muons and the so-called relativistic corrections for GPS, whose explanation is commonly provided by resorting to Einstein’s Relativity. To make the discussion more flowing, we have herein preferred to completely avoid the writing of equations. All the analytical solutions, as well as several explicative figures, can be found in the first six articles cited in the references, drafted by the same author of this manuscript.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
11

Brendle, Jörg. "Amoeba-absoluteness and projective measurability." Journal of Symbolic Logic 58, no. 4 (December 1993): 1284–90. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2275143.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
12

Bagaria, Joan, and Roger Bosch. "Generic absoluteness under projective forcing." Fundamenta Mathematicae 194, no. 2 (2007): 95–120. http://dx.doi.org/10.4064/fm194-2-1.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
13

Ikegami, Daisuke. "Projective absoluteness for Sacks forcing." Archive for Mathematical Logic 48, no. 7 (September 12, 2009): 679–90. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s00153-009-0143-5.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
14

Todorcevic, Stevo. "Generic Absoluteness and the Continuum." Mathematical Research Letters 9, no. 4 (2002): 465–71. http://dx.doi.org/10.4310/mrl.2002.v9.n4.a6.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
15

Ikegami, Daisuke. "Forcing absoluteness and regularity properties." Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161, no. 7 (April 2010): 879–94. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.apal.2009.10.005.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
16

WILSON, TREVOR M. "UNIVERSALLY BAIRE SETS AND GENERIC ABSOLUTENESS." Journal of Symbolic Logic 82, no. 4 (December 2017): 1229–51. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/jsl.2017.35.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractWe prove several equivalences and relative consistency results regarding generic absoluteness beyond Woodin’s ${\left( {{\bf{\Sigma }}_1^2} \right)^{{\rm{u}}{{\rm{B}}_\lambda }}}$ generic absoluteness result for a limit of Woodin cardinals λ. In particular, we prove that two-step $\exists ^ℝ \left( {{\rm{\Pi }}_1^2 } \right)^{{\rm{uB}}_\lambda } $ generic absoluteness below a measurable limit of Woodin cardinals has high consistency strength and is equivalent, modulo small forcing, to the existence of trees for ${\left( {{\bf{\Pi }}_1^2} \right)^{{\rm{u}}{{\rm{B}}_\lambda }}}$ formulas. The construction of these trees uses a general method for building an absolute complement for a given tree T assuming many “failures of covering” for the models $L\left( {T,{V_\alpha }} \right)$ for α below a measurable cardinal.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
17

Kopinska, Agnieszka, and Laurence R. Harris. "Simultaneity Constancy." Perception 33, no. 9 (September 2004): 1049–60. http://dx.doi.org/10.1068/p5169.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
18

Marvell, Thomas B. "Indirect simultaneity." Criminology & Public Policy 18, no. 1 (February 2019): 201–6. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/1745-9133.12432.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
19

Schindler, Ralf-Dieter. "Proper forcing and remarkable cardinals II." Journal of Symbolic Logic 66, no. 3 (September 2001): 1481–92. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2695120.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractThe current paper proves the results announced in [5].We isolate a new large cardinal concept, “remarkability.” Consistencywise, remarkable cardinals are between ineffable and ω-Erdös cardinals. They are characterized by the existence of “0#-like” embeddings; however, they relativize down to L. It turns out that the existence of a remarkable cardinal is equiconsistent with L(ℝ) absoluteness for proper forcings. In particular, said absoluteness does not imply determinacy.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
20

Hjorth, Greg. "An absoluteness principle for Borel sets." Journal of Symbolic Logic 63, no. 2 (June 1998): 663–93. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2586857.

Full text
Abstract:
The purpose of these notes is to describe an absoluteness principle due to Jacques Stern and discuss some applications to the general study of Borel sets. This paper will not be engaged in independence results, but in proving outright theorems about the Borel hierarchy.Roughly speaking, Stern's absoluteness principle states that if a certain set can be introduced into the universe by forcing, then it can be introduced by some small forcing notion.The notation , and so on, will be defined in Section 1; this gives a notational system for describing the complexity of Borel sets beyond Fσ or Gδ. The “universe” refers to the totality of all sets. “Forcing” refers to Paul Cohen's technique for, in some sense, changing this totality by the introduction of new sets. Here “small” means relatively small cardinality.The size of this small forcing notion is roughly the ath iteration of the power set operation. Just to get an idea of what this theorem might be saying, we can argue that under certain conditions, if a closed set can be introduced by forcing, then it exists already. There are a number of other qualifications that need to be made to this rough description, and we will come to them later.Unlike, say, Shoenfield absoluteness, Stern's absoluteness can only be made understood in the terminology of forcing. Since forcing is typically associated with the pursuit of independence results, we could easily assume that Stern's work has little relevance in proving positive theorems about the Borel hierarchy.However, this would be untrue. Using abstract and indirect metamathematical arguments, and availing ourselves of Stern's absoluteness principle, we will prove a string of ZFC theorems for which no direct proof is known.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
21

Nikolic, Dusan. "Absoluteness of ownership in French law." Zbornik radova Pravnog fakulteta, Novi Sad 48, no. 4 (2014): 85–101. http://dx.doi.org/10.5937/zrpfns48-7571.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
22

Halbeisen, Lorenz, and Haim Judah. "Mathias absoluteness and the Ramsey property." Journal of Symbolic Logic 61, no. 1 (March 1996): 177–94. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2275603.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractIn this article we give a forcing characterization for the Ramsey property of -Sets of reals. This research was motivated by the well-known forcing characterizations for Lebesgue measurability and the Baire property of -sets of reals. Further we will show the relationship between higher degrees of forcing absoluteness and the Ramsey property of projective sets of reals.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
23

Kanovei, V. G., and V. A. Lyubetsky. "Absoluteness of the Solovay Set Σ." Siberian Mathematical Journal 60, no. 6 (November 2019): 1003–6. http://dx.doi.org/10.1134/s0037446619060089.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
24

Hauser, Kai. "The consistency strength of projective absoluteness." Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 74, no. 3 (August 1995): 245–95. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/0168-0072(94)00041-z.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
25

FUCHS, GUNTER, and KAETHE MINDEN. "SUBCOMPLETE FORCING, TREES, AND GENERIC ABSOLUTENESS." Journal of Symbolic Logic 83, no. 3 (September 2018): 1282–305. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/jsl.2018.23.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractWe investigate properties of trees of height ω1 and their preservation under subcomplete forcing. We show that subcomplete forcing cannot add a new branch to an ω1-tree. We introduce fragments of subcompleteness which are preserved by subcomplete forcing, and use these in order to show that certain strong forms of rigidity of Suslin trees are preserved by subcomplete forcing. Finally, we explore under what circumstances subcomplete forcing preserves Aronszajn trees of height and width ω1. We show that this is the case if CH fails, and if CH holds, then this is the case iff the bounded subcomplete forcing axiom holds. Finally, we explore the relationships between bounded forcing axioms, preservation of Aronszajn trees of height and width ω1 and generic absoluteness of ${\rm{\Sigma }}_1^1$-statements over first order structures of size ω1, also for other canonical classes of forcing.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
26

Seki, Shinnosuke. "Absoluteness of subword inequality is undecidable." Theoretical Computer Science 418 (February 2012): 116–20. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.tcs.2011.10.017.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
27

Moreno, George, Ranieri Nery, Cristhiano Duarte, and Rafael Chaves. "Events in quantum mechanics are maximally non-absolute." Quantum 6 (August 24, 2022): 785. http://dx.doi.org/10.22331/q-2022-08-24-785.

Full text
Abstract:
The notorious quantum measurement problem brings out the difficulty to reconcile two quantum postulates: the unitary evolution of closed quantum systems and the wave-function collapse after a measurement. This problematics is particularly highlighted in the Wigner's friend thought experiment, where the mismatch between unitary evolution and measurement collapse leads to conflicting quantum descriptions for different observers. A recent no-go theorem has established that the (quantum) statistics arising from an extended Wigner's friend scenario is incompatible when one try to hold together three innocuous assumptions, namely no-superdeterminism, parameter independence and absoluteness of observed events. Building on this extended scenario, we introduce two novel measures of non-absoluteness of events. The first is based on the EPR2 decomposition, and the second involves the relaxation of the absoluteness hypothesis assumed in the aforementioned no-go theorem. To prove that quantum correlations can be maximally non-absolute according to both quantifiers, we show that chained Bell inequalities (and relaxations thereof) are also valid constraints for Wigner's experiment.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
28

Leftow, Brian. "Eternity and Simultaneity." Faith and Philosophy 8, no. 2 (1991): 148–79. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/faithphil19918220.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
29

Hadler, Florian, and Daniel Irrgang. "Nonlinearity, Multilinearity, Simultaneity." Interactive Film and Media Journal 1, no. 2 (November 22, 2021): 5–32. http://dx.doi.org/10.32920/ifmj.v1i2.1497.

Full text
Abstract:
This paper addresses three paradigms in epistemological structures that could serve as preliminary classifications enabling a systematic approach to past and current media phenomena such as hypertext, diagrams and ubiquitous computing. Nonlinearity is discussed by Vilém Flusser in the context of "technical images." In his own approach to go beyond linear text, Flusser and his publisher created a digital version of his book Die Schrift on a floppy disk (1987), enabling the reader to jump between chapters or to rewrite the text. Multilinearity is a concept that is revived within the diagrammatology discourse, transcending linearity through topographical ways of reading. Current examples can be found in arts and narratives such as Chris Ware's comics, who uses diagrammatics to blur the lines between the reader and the author. Simultaneity as a technological attribute is essential to current ubiquitous and pervasive technologies and services and draws heavily on Heideggerian concepts such as readiness-to-hand and background. In this epistemological shift, the information is instantaneously organized according to the user's needs. Each of these epistemological structures offers a different idea about receiving and creating knowledge, information and communication, paving the way for narrative and media strategies that are more and more determined by a 'reader' becoming a 'user' and a 'text' becoming a 'service.' Image Credit: Chris Ware’s Diagram on the interior of the dust-jacket from Jimmy Corrigan, The Smartest Kid on Earth.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
30

Orji, Anthony, and Peter N. Mba. "Testing for Simultaneity." Journal of Infrastructure Development 2, no. 2 (December 2010): 105–20. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/097493061100200202.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
31

McCrossen, Alexis. "“Conventions of Simultaneity”." Journal of Urban History 33, no. 2 (January 2007): 217–53. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0096144206294738.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
32

Giulini, Domenico. "Uniqueness of Simultaneity." British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 52, no. 4 (December 1, 2001): 651–70. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/bjps/52.4.651.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
33

Cohen, Michael. "Einstein on Simultaneity." Philosophy 67, no. 262 (October 1992): 543–48. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0031819100040705.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
34

Tokuo, Kenji. "Logic of Simultaneity." International Journal of Theoretical Physics 48, no. 5 (November 18, 2008): 1290–99. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10773-008-9900-1.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
35

Adler, Charles L. "Magnetism and Simultaneity." Physics Teacher 47, no. 4 (April 2009): 221–23. http://dx.doi.org/10.1119/1.3098206.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
36

Arkhipova, I. V. "Iterative-Taxis Intercategorial Interaction in German and Russian." Bulletin of Kemerovo State University 24, no. 2 (May 17, 2022): 194–202. http://dx.doi.org/10.21603/2078-8975-2022-24-2-194-202.

Full text
Abstract:
The article features iterative-taxis categorical situations of simultaneity and non-simultaneity in German and Russian. The functional and semantic categories of taxis and iteration are closely interrelated. The intersection and syncretic unification of these functional-semantic categories makes it possible to define the model of their intercategorial interaction as a model of intercategorical crossing. Intercategorical crossing of taxis and iterative categories determines the actualization of various iterative-taxis categorical situations of simultaneity and non-simultaneity. They are actualized in iterative statements of various subtypes, e.g., verbal-iterative, deverbial-iterative, attributive-iterative, adverbial-iterative, etc., which contain iterative deverbatives, iterative verbs, and iterative quantifiers, i.e., attributes and adverbials. German and Russian proved to have such varieties of iterative-taxis categorial situations of simultaneity and non-simultaneity as (1) deverbative-iterative, (2) verbaliterative, and (3) adverbial-iterative and attributive-iterative. Actualization of certain iterative-taxis categorial situations of simultaneity and non-simultaneity depends on genetically-iterative, genetically-multiplicative, and word-formation-iterative deverbatives, as well as on iterative verbs of different semantics (actual iteratives, diminutives, multiplicatives, distributives, etc.) and iterative quantifiers (attributes and adverbials).
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
37

Arkhipova, Irina V. "Actualization of Taxis Situations Localized/Non-Localized in Time (Based on German Utterances with Prepositional Deverbatives)." Vestnik of Northern (Arctic) Federal University. Series Humanitarian and Social Sciences, no. 4 (October 15, 2022): 37–45. http://dx.doi.org/10.37482/2687-1505-v189.

Full text
Abstract:
This article dwells on the actualization of various categorial taxis situations of simultaneity and non-simultaneity of actions localized and non-localized in time in modern German. The material included German utterances with prepositional deverbatives obtained by continuous sampling from the Digital Dictionary of the German Language (Digitales Wörterbuch der deutschen Sprache) and Leipzig Corpora Collection (Wortschatz Leipzig). The total number of examined fragments exceeded 7000. The following methods were used: descriptive, inductive, hypothetical-deductive, classification method, generalization and interpretation of linguistic material, as well as corpus and contextual analysis. The functional-semantic categories of taxis and temporary localization/non-localization considered here are closely interconnected with each other. The author defines their intercategorial interaction as intercategorial crossing, which determines the actualization of different variants of categorial taxis situations of simultaneity and non-simultaneity. In utterances with prepositional deverbatives, two types of categorial taxis situations are possible, relevant in terms of intercategorial crossing of the categories of taxis and temporal localization/ non-localization: 1) specific (localized in time); 2) non-specific (non-localized). The research found that in German utterances with prepositional deverbatives, interconnected categorial temporal-taxis, iterative-taxis and phase-taxis situations of simultaneity and non-simultaneity of localized/non-localized actions (processes, events) can be actualized. The plurality of specific subjects or objects of verbal actions, as well as various temporal, aspectual, iterative, taxis, local/temporal-local explicators (monocomponent, bicomponent and multicomponent), assume a prototypical character. Temporal explicators participate in the expression of categorial taxis situations of simultaneity and non-simultaneity of actions localized in time with “exact” or “approximate” indication of the time of their implementation or course. Local/ temporal-local explicators represent categorial taxis situations of simultaneity and non-simultaneity of actions (processes, events) localized in time, indicating their exact location in space or time. Iterative explicators (attributes, adverbials) determine the categorial iterative-taxis situations of simultaneity and non-simultaneity of actions (processes, events) that are not localized in time.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
38

Braaten, Carle E. "The Problem of the Absoluteness of Christianity." Interpretation: A Journal of Bible and Theology 40, no. 4 (October 1986): 341–53. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/002096438604000402.

Full text
Abstract:
The absoluteness of Christianity is a predicate of the God of the eschatological kingdom proclaimed by Jesus, a kingdom embracing the power of a universal future which also includes the entire sweep of the history of religions.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
39

Pahlavan, Farzaneh, and Ali Amirrezvani. "Contextual freedom: Absoluteness versus relativity of freedom." Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36, no. 5 (August 29, 2013): 498–99. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0140525x13000204.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractOur commentary is focused on the idea that “freedom” takes on its full significance whenever its relativistic nature, in the short- and long terms, is taken into account. Given the transformations brought about by “globalization,” application of a general model of freedom based on ecological-economic factors clearly seems to be rather untimely. We examine this idea through egocentric and ethnocentric views of the social and environmental analyses of “freedom.”
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
40

Yuanshun, Chin. "Relativistic absoluteness of time-space-moving mass." Applied Mathematics and Mechanics 16, no. 7 (July 1995): 611–14. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/bf02455244.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
41

Morvarid, Hashem. "Hale on the Absoluteness of Logical Necessity." Acta Analytica 32, no. 1 (March 22, 2016): 1–11. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s12136-016-0290-3.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
42

Zampini, Massimiliano, Steve Guest, David I. Shore, and Charles Spence. "Audio-visual simultaneity judgments." Perception & Psychophysics 67, no. 3 (April 2005): 531–44. http://dx.doi.org/10.3758/bf03193329.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
43

Terin, V. P. "Politics Under Electronic Simultaneity." MGIMO Review of International Relations, no. 1(34) (February 28, 2014): 37–44. http://dx.doi.org/10.24833/2071-8160-2014-1-34-37-44.

Full text
Abstract:
In contradistinction to the book and the other typographic products, the electronic media operates on a 24-hour-a-day basis evoking simultaneity as the guiding mode of perception and thinking for all those under its influence. The discovery of this fact manifested itself in the formation and development of the managerial technologies operating by means of the electronic information environment and following the principle of simultaneity in the first place. Thus, at the end of the 1960s already the election campaigns in the U.S.A. began to operate on the basis of the final cause as the guiding principle of the country's mass consciousness motivating to carry out each particular event as if already rejoicing at the victory. With this in mind, there emerged a problem of applying this approach with its enormous managerial potential elsewhere. To add, simultaneity as a norm of perception and thinking turned out to be increasingly important with the advent of the electrical telegraph and the press relying on its short disconnected messages instantaneously arriving from all parts of the world. All the other media, which emerged in the wake of this development, has served to fortify this mode of thought as governing in the electronic information environment. The potential of the electronically operating global managerial technologies is quickly growing. The article also deals with the information overload and pattern recognition problem understood in managerial terms as well as mythologization and demythologization processes as they are necessitated by the electronic media coverage worldwide.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
44

Harada, Minoru. "Collapse of relative simultaneity." Physics Essays 22, no. 2 (June 1, 2009): 168–70. http://dx.doi.org/10.4006/1.3120915.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
45

Lee, Chunghyoung. "Simultaneity in cylindrical spacetime." American Journal of Physics 88, no. 2 (February 2020): 131–36. http://dx.doi.org/10.1119/10.0000002.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
46

Fujisaki, Waka, Shinsuke Shimojo, Makio Kashino, and Shin'ya Nishida. "Recalibration of audiovisual simultaneity." Nature Neuroscience 7, no. 7 (June 13, 2004): 773–78. http://dx.doi.org/10.1038/nn1268.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
47

Tugby, Matthew. "SIMULTANEITY IN DISPOSITIONAL INTERACTION?" Ratio 23, no. 3 (July 21, 2010): 322–38. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9329.2010.00470.x.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
48

White, V. Alan. "Relativity and Simultaneity Redux." Philosophy 68, no. 265 (July 1993): 401–4. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0031819100041310.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
49

Cohen, Michael. "Simultaneity and Einstein's Gedankenexperiment." Philosophy 64, no. 249 (July 1989): 391–96. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0031819100044739.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
50

Cohen, Michael. "Simultaneity: A Composite Rejoinder." Philosophy 70, no. 274 (October 1995): 587–89. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0031819100065839.

Full text
Abstract:
V. Alan White and Gertrud Walton have published responses to my note on Einstein's simultaneity Gedankenexperiment, in which I present a version of the argument free of the flaws to be found in that given by Einstein. White thinks I go too far, that no reformulation is necessary; Walton, that I don't go far enough, and that i the inconsistencies in Einstein's exposition are ‘irreconcilable’. I r shall try to explain why I think both are mistaken.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
We offer discounts on all premium plans for authors whose works are included in thematic literature selections. Contact us to get a unique promo code!

To the bibliography