Dissertations / Theses on the topic 'Philosophy and explanation'
Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles
Consult the top 50 dissertations / theses for your research on the topic 'Philosophy and explanation.'
Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.
You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.
Browse dissertations / theses on a wide variety of disciplines and organise your bibliography correctly.
Quinn, Laleh Kathleen. "Consciousness and explanation." Diss., The University of Arizona, 2000. http://hdl.handle.net/10150/289172.
Full textNickel, Bernhard Ph D. Massachusetts Institute of Technology. "Truth in explanation." Thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 2005. http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/33711.
Full textIncludes bibliographical references (p. 155-163).
My thesis consists of three papers on truth and explanations in science. Broadly, the question I ask is semantic. Should the best account of certain bits of our scientific practice focus on the concept of truth? More specifically, should the crucial distinctions between good and bad aspects of that practice be drawn in terms of truth? My thesis consists of three case studies: ceteris paribus laws in the special sciences, appeals to idealizations in the application of theories, and the analysis of explanations quite generally, exemplified in the asymmetry of explanation. In each case, prominent philosophers have argued that a proper treatment does not focus on truth. In each case, I argue that truth should play a central role. And in each case, the issue turns, at least in part, on the connection between the scientific practice in question and explanations.
by Bernhard Nickel.
Ph.D.
Ooms, Renard Nicole Marie Anne. "Plato's metaphysics of explanation." Thesis, King's College London (University of London), 1999. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.324884.
Full textLipton, P. "Explanation and evidence." Thesis, University of Oxford, 1985. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.371691.
Full textWhite, Roger (Roger Lewis) 1967. "Probability, explanation, and reasoning." Thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 2000. http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/8841.
Full textIncludes bibliographical references (p. 96).
Three topics are discussed concerning the application probability and explanation to the confirmation of theories. The first concerns the debate over prediction versus accommodation. I argue that we typically have reason to be more confident of a theory given that it was constructed independently of the knowledge of certain data than if it was designed to accommodate those data. The second concerns the puzzle of the apparent 'fine-tuning' of the universe for life. I argue that the fact that our universe meets the extremely improbable yet necessary conditions for life provides no evidence for the thesis that there are, or have been, very many universes. The third chapter concerns the need to explain the existence of life. I argue that if life's existence needs an explanation at all, the place to look is in a teleological explanation. If this option is rejected, we should be content to see the origin of life as an extremely improbable fluke.
by Roger White.
Ph.D.
Patterson, Sarah Charlotte. "Content and psychological explanation." Thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 1988. http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/13941.
Full textEmery, Nina R. (Nina Rebecca). "Chance, indeterminacy, and explanation." Thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 2012. http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/72921.
Full text"June 2012." Cataloged from PDF version of thesis.
Includes bibliographical references (p. 97-101).
This thesis is about the philosophical and scientific significance of chance. Specifically, I ask whether there is a single notion of chance that both plays a well-defined scientific role and proves useful for various philosophical projects. I argue that there is, but that this notion of chance is importantly different from the one that we usually come across in the philosophical literature. In the first chapter, "Chance, Indeterminacy, and Explanation", I argue against the common and influential view that chances are those probabilities that arise when the fundamental laws are indeterministic. The problem with this view, I claim, is not that it conflicts with some antecedently plausible metaphysics of chance, but rather that it renders the distinction between chance and other sorts of probability incapable of playing any scientifically significant role. I suggest an alternative view, according to which chances are the probabilities that play a certain explanatory role-they are probabilities that explain associated frequencies. In the second chapter, "Chance, Explanation, and Measure", I build on the view that chances are the probabilities that play a certain explanatory role by developing an account of non-fundamental chances-chances that arise when the fundamental laws are deterministic. On this account, non-fundamental chances are objective measures over relevant classes of alternative possibilities. In the third chapter, "Chance and Counterfactuals", I show how the sort of chances I have argued for can play an important role in a very different sort of philosophical project. According to a number of recent arguments, one consequence of our current scientific theories is that most ordinary counterfactuals are not true. I argue that the best response to these arguments makes use of the non-fundamental chances that I have argued for in the first two chapters of the dissertation.
by Nina R. Emery.
Ph.D.in Philosophy
Kazez, Jean Rahel. "Mental representation and causal explanation." Diss., The University of Arizona, 1990. http://hdl.handle.net/10150/185312.
Full textSutton, Peter Andrew. "Models of scientific explanation." Texas A&M University, 2005. http://hdl.handle.net/1969.1/2372.
Full textDeulofeu, Batllori Roger. "Scientific explanation in biology. Beyond mechanistic explanation." Doctoral thesis, Universitat de Barcelona, 2020. http://hdl.handle.net/10803/668748.
Full textCifone, Michael C. "Structuralism and natural philosophy method, metaphysics and explanation /." College Park, Md.: University of Maryland, 2009. http://hdl.handle.net/1903/9479.
Full textThesis research directed by: Dept. of Philosophy. Title from t.p. of PDF. Includes bibliographical references. Published by UMI Dissertation Services, Ann Arbor, Mich. Also available in paper.
Dixon, Joan Elizabeth. "Time, consciousness and scientific explanation." Thesis, University of Warwick, 1997. http://wrap.warwick.ac.uk/4309/.
Full textStout, Rowland. "The teleological explanation of action." Thesis, University of Oxford, 1991. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:0f9add24-82bb-4777-b2c4-669262f2015b.
Full textFlockemann, Richard. "Externalism, self-knowledge and explanation." Thesis, Rhodes University, 2013. http://hdl.handle.net/10962/d1008060.
Full textKMBT_363
Adobe Acrobat 9.54 Paper Capture Plug-in
McIntosh, Jillian Scott. "Teleological functionalism, normativity, explanation, and the philosophy of mind." Thesis, National Library of Canada = Bibliothèque nationale du Canada, 1997. http://www.collectionscanada.ca/obj/s4/f2/dsk3/ftp04/nq25111.pdf.
Full textHershfield, Jeffrey Allan. "Reduction and explanation in the theory of content." Diss., The University of Arizona, 1992. http://hdl.handle.net/10150/186022.
Full textTaylor, Kaetlin Diane. "The Epistemic and Ontic Conceptions of Scientific Explanation." Thesis, Virginia Tech, 2017. http://hdl.handle.net/10919/78011.
Full textMaster of Arts
Kostko, Aaron. "Epistemic and Nonepistemic Values in Psychiatric Explanation and Classification." University of Cincinnati / OhioLINK, 2014. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc_num=ucin1396522414.
Full textChiba, Kei. "Aristotle on explanation : demonstrative science and scientific inquiry." Thesis, University of Oxford, 1989. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.303539.
Full textButchart, Samuel John 1971. "Evidence and explanation in mathematics." Monash University, Dept. of Philosophy, 2001. http://arrow.monash.edu.au/hdl/1959.1/8616.
Full textReinisch, Peter. "Locke's theory of justified resistance an explanation and defense." Thesis, State University of New York at Albany, 2014. http://pqdtopen.proquest.com/#viewpdf?dispub=3620241.
Full textOne of the main goals of John Locke's Second Treatise Of Government, is to explain when it is morally permissible for someone to resist their government with force. I call this "John Locke's Theory of Justified Resistance." How Locke derived this theory was be weaving together his thoughts about the nature of God, the law of nature, human nature, human understanding, natural rights, human history, and government. The result is what I think to be and what I hope to prove is a comprehensive and internally coherent moral theory. The theory provides for us the conditions and circumstances in which someone is morally justified to resist their government. Although Locke's theory has been very influential it has not been without its critics. Some of the criticisms have been answered and some have not. In my dissertation I provide answers to the critics. How I answer the critics is by either explaining the theory or by explaining the relevant aspects of Locke's thought that come into play in a given situation. The best way to do those two things is to appeal most often to Locke's own words. Locke is his best defender. Besides explaining the theory and providing answers to the critics, I also examine hypothetical and historical cases studies and apply Locke's theory to them. These case studies test Locke's theory and they allow us to see both the strength and the relevance of the theory, while also helping us gain a deeper understanding of the theory. In the end I offer my own disagreement and criticism of the theory, but I think without undermining Locke's great achievement of giving us an invaluable theory of justified resistance.
Lusk, Gregory S. "Models and scientific explanation." Ohio : Ohio University, 2009. http://www.ohiolink.edu/etd/view.cgi?ohiou1250816101.
Full textCrawford, Michael Sean. "The nature of commonsense psychological explanation." Thesis, University of Oxford, 1999. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:db4cf477-2203-4f06-a8f4-b56f65840366.
Full textGordon, Richard Douglas. "Explanation and prediction in the labour process theory." Thesis, University of British Columbia, 1990. http://hdl.handle.net/2429/30583.
Full textArts, Faculty of
Philosophy, Department of
Graduate
Rivelli, Luca. "Modularity, antimodularity and explanation in complex systems." Thesis, Paris 1, 2015. http://www.theses.fr/2015PA010529/document.
Full textThis work is mainly concerned with the notion of hierarchical modularity and its use in explaining structure and dynamical behavior of complex systems by means of hierarchical modular models, as well as with a concept of my proposal, antimodularity, tied to the possibility of the algorithmic detection of hierarchical modularity. Specifically, I highlight the pragmatic bearing of hierarchical modularity on the possibility of scientific explanation of complex systems, that is, systems which, according to a chosen basic description, can be considered as composed of elementary, discrete, interrelated parts. I stress that hierarchical modularity is also required by the experimentation aimed to discover the structure of such systems. Algorithmic detection of hierarchical modularity turns out to be a task plagued by the demonstrated computational intractability of the search for the best hierarchical modular description, and by the high computational expensiveness of even approximated detection methods. Antimodularity consists in the lack of a modular description fitting the needs of the observer, a lack due either to absence of modularity in the system’s chosen basic description, or to the impossibility, due to the excessive size of the system under assessment in relation to the computational cost of algorithmic methods, to algorithmically produce a valid hierarchical description. I stress that modularity and antimodularity depend on the pragmatic choice of a given basic description of the system, a choice made by the observer based on explanatory goals. I show how antimodularity hinders the possibility of applying at least three well-known types of explanation: mechanistic, deductive-nomological and computational. A fourth type, topological explanation, remains unaffected. I then assess the presence of modularity in biological systems, and evaluate the possible consequences, and the likelihood, of incurring in antimodularity in biology and other sciences, concluding that this eventuality is quite likely, at least in systems biology. I finally indulge in some metaphysical and historical speculations: metaphysically, antimodularity seems to suggest a possible position according to which natural kinds are detected modules, and as such, due to the computational hardness of the detection of the best hierarchical modular description, they are unlikely to be the best possible way to describe the world, because the modularity of natural kinds quite probably does not reflect the best possible modularity of the world. From an historical point of view, the growing use of computational methods for modularity detection or simulation of complex systems, especially in certain areas of scientific research, hints at the envisioning of a multiplicity of emerging scientific disciplines guided by a self- sustained, growing production of possibly human-unintelligible explanations. This, I suggest, would constitute an historical change in science, which, if has not already occurred, could well be on the verge of happening
Questo lavoro riguarda principalmente il concetto di modularità gerarchica e il suo impiego nello spiegare la struttura e il comportamento dinamico di sistemi complessi mediante modelli modulari gerarchici, nonché un concetto di mia proposta, l’antimodularità, legato alla possibilità del rilevamento algoritmico di modularità gerarchica. Nello specifico, evidenzio la portata pragmatica della modularità gerarchica sulla possibilità di spiegazione scientifica dei sistemi complessi, cioè sistemi che, secondo una descrizione di base scelta dall’osservatore, possono essere considerati come composti da parti elementari discrete interrelate. Sottolineo che la modularità gerarchica è essenziale anche nel corso della sperimentazione volta a scoprire la struttura di tali sistemi. Il rilevamento algoritmico della modularità gerarchica si rivela essere un compito affetto dalla dimostrata intrattabilità computazionale della ricerca della migliore descrizione modulare gerarchica, e affetto dal comunque elevato costo computazionale anche dei metodi di rilevamento approssimati della modularità. L’antimodularità consiste nella mancanza di una descrizione modulare adatta alle esigenze dell’osservatore, mancanza dovuta o all’assenza di modularità nella descrizione di base del sistema scelta dall’osservatore, o all’impossibilità di produrre algoritmicamente una sua descrizione gerarchica valida, per le dimensioni eccessive del sistema da valutare in rapporto al costo computazionale dei metodi algoritmici. Sottolineo che modularità e antimodularità dipendono dalla scelta pragmatica di una certa descrizione di base del sistema, scelta fatta dall’osservatore sulla base di obiettivi esplicativi. Mostro poi come l’antimodularità ostacoli la possibilità di applicare almeno tre tipi noti di spiegazione: meccanicistica, deduttivo- nomologica e computazionale. Un quarto tipo di spiegazione, la spiegazione topologica, rimane sostanzialmente immune dalle conseguenze dell’antimodularità. Valuto quindi la presenza di modularità nei sistemi biologici, e le sue possibili conseguenze, nonché l’eventualità di incorrere nell’antimodularità in biologia e in altre scienze, concludendo che questa eventualità è abbastanza probabile, almeno in biologia dei sistemi. Infine, mi permetto alcune speculazioni metafisiche e storiche piuttosto libere. Dal punto di vista metafisico, l’antimodularità sembra suggerire una posizione possibile secondo cui i generi naturali sono moduli che sono stati rilevati, e in quanto tali, a causa dell’intrattabilità computazionale del rilevamento della migliore descrizione modulare gerarchica, è improbabile che essi siano il miglior modo possibile per descrivere il mondo, perché la modularità dei generi naturali molto probabilmente non rispecchia la migliore modularità possibile del mondo. Da un punto di vista storico, il crescente utilizzo di metodi computazionali per il rilevamento della modularità o per la simulazione di sistemi complessi, in particolare in alcuni settori della ricerca scientifica, suggerisce la possibilità di immaginare una molteplicità di discipline scientifiche emergenti, guidate dalla produzione di spiegazioni potenzialmente inintelligibili dal punto di vista cognitivo umano, produzione che potrebbe iniziare ad autoalimentarsi, portando potenzialmente ad una crescita inarrestabile. Suggerisco che questo scenario cos- tituirebbe un cambiamento epocale nel campo della scienza, che, se non è già avvenuto, potrebbe benissimo essere sul punto di realizzarsi
QUILLEN, KEITH RAYMOND. "PROPOSITIONAL ATTITUDES AND PSYCHOLOGICAL EXPLANATION (MIND, MENTAL)." Diss., The University of Arizona, 1985. http://hdl.handle.net/10150/188053.
Full textJohansson, Erik. "Testing the Explanation Hypothesis using Experimental Methods." Thesis, Linköping University, Department of Computer and Information Science, 2010. http://urn.kb.se/resolve?urn=urn:nbn:se:liu:diva-57308.
Full textThe Explanation Hypothesis is a psychological hypothesis about how people attribute moral responsibility. The hypothesis makes general claims about everyday thinking of moral responsibility and is also said to have important consequences for related philosophical issues. Since arguments in favor of the hypothesis are largely based on a number of intuitive cases, there is need to investigate whether it is supported by empirical evidence. In this study, the hypothesis was tested by means of quantitative experimental methods. The data were collected by conducting online surveys in which participants were introduced to a number of different scenarios. For each scenario, questions about moral responsibility were asked. Results provide general support for the Explanation Hypothesis and there are therefore more reasons to take its proposed consequences seriously.
Wynn, Mark. "God and the world : the place of explanation in natural theology." Thesis, University of Oxford, 1991. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.316018.
Full textFloyd, Jonathan. "The Impossibility Thesis : A methodological explanation of interminability in contemporary political philosophy." Thesis, University of Oxford, 2009. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.517133.
Full textDawes, Gregory W., and n/a. "Theism and explanation : a defence of scientific naturalism." University of Otago. Department of Philosophy, 2007. http://adt.otago.ac.nz./public/adt-NZDU20070815.134617.
Full textPacer, Michael D. "Mind as Theory Engine| Causation, Explanation and Time." Thesis, University of California, Berkeley, 2017. http://pqdtopen.proquest.com/#viewpdf?dispub=10194103.
Full textHumans build theories out of the data we observe, and out of those theories arise wonders. The most powerful theories are causal theories, which organise data into actionable structures. Causal theories make explicit claims about the structure of the world: what entities and processes exist in it, which of these relate to one another and in what form those relations consist. We can use causal theories to induce new generalisations about the world (in the form of particular models or other causal theories) and to explain particular occurrences. This allows rapidly disseminating causal information throughout our cognitive communities. Causal theories and the explanations derived from them guide decisions we make, including where and when to look for more data, completing the cycle.
Causal theories play a ubiquitous and potent role in everyday life, in formal pursuit of them in the sciences, and through their applications in medicine, technology and industry. Given this, the rarity of analyses that attempt to characterise causal theories and their uses in general, computational terms is surprising. Only in recent years has there been a substantial refinement of our models of causal induction due to work by computational cognitive scientists — the interdisciplinary tradition out of which which this dissertation originates. And even so, many issues related to causal theories have been left unattended; three features in particular merit much greater attention from a computational perspective: generating and evaluating explanation, the role of simplicity in explanation choice, and continuous-time causal induction. I aim to redress this situation with this dissertation.
In Chapter 0, I introduce the primary paradigms from computational cognitive science – computational level analysis and rational analysis – that govern my research. In Chapter 1, I study formal theories of causal explanation in Bayesian networks by comparing the explanations the generate and evaluate to human judgements about the same systems. No one model of causal explanation captures the pattern of human judgements, though the intuitive hypothesis, that the most probable a posteriori explanation is the best performs worst of the models evaluated. I conclude that the premise of finding model for all of human causal explanation (even in this limited domain) is flawed; the research programme should be refined to consider the features of formal models and how well they capture our explanatory practices as they vary between individuals and circumstances. One feature not expressed in these models explicitly but that has been shown to matter for human explanation is simplicity. Chapter 2 considers the problem of simplicity in human causal explanation choice in a series of four experiments. I study what makes an explanation simple (whether it is the number of causes invoked in or the number of assumptions made by an explanation), how simplicity concerns are traded off against data-fit, which cognitive consequences arise from choosing simpler explanations when the data does not fit, and why people prefer simpler explanations.
In Chapter 3, I change the focus from studying causal explanation to causal induction — in particular, I develop a framework for continuous time causal theories (
CTCTS
). ACTCT
defines a generative probabilistic framework for other generative probabilistic models of causal systems, where the data in those systems expressed in terms of continuous time. Chapter 3 is the most interdisciplinary piece of my dissertation, accordingly it begins by reviewing a number of topics: the history of theories of causal induction within philosophy, statistics and medicine; empirical work on causal induction in cognitive science, focusing on issues related to causal induction with temporal data; conceptual issues surrounding the formal definition of time, data, and causal models; and probabilistic graphical models, causal theories, and stochastic processes. I then introduce the desiderata for theCTCT
framework and how those criteria are met. I then demonstrate the power ofCTCTS
by using them to analyse five sets of experiments (some new and some derived from the literature) on human causal induction with temporal data. Bookending each experiment and the model applied to it is are case from medical history that illustrate a real-world instance of the variety of problem being solved in the section; the opening discussion describes the case and why it fits the problem structure of the model used to analyse the experimental results and the closing discussion illustrates aspects of the case omitted from the initial discussion that complicate the model and fit better with the model introduced in the next section. Then, I discuss ways to incorporate other advances in probabilistic programming, generative theories and stochastic processes into theCTCT
framework, identify potential applications with specific focus on mechanisms and feedback loops, and conclude by analysing the centrality of temporal information in the study of the mind more generally.Excepting the supporting appendices and bibliography that end the dissertation, I conclude in two parts. First, in Chapter 4, I analyse issues at the intersection of three of the main themes of my work: namely, (causal) explanation, (causal) induction and time. This proceeds by examining these topics first in pairs and then as a whole. Following that, is Chapter 5, an epilogue that clarifies the interpretations and intended meanings of the “Mind as Theory Engine” metaphor as it applies to human cognition.
Montuschi, Eleonora. "Scientific metaphor and theoretical explanation : an inquiry into the constructive language of postulation." Thesis, University of Oxford, 1988. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.304916.
Full textWright, Christopher Robert. "An explanation of knowledge and its relation to some problems in contemporary epistemology." Thesis, University of Cambridge, 1990. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.385469.
Full textKnowles, Jonathan Lewis. "Explanation, tacit knowledge, and language : an inquiry into the philosophical significance of cognitive science." Thesis, Birkbeck (University of London), 1995. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.243376.
Full textKnowles, Robert Frazer. "Towards a fictionalist philosophy of mathematics." Thesis, University of Manchester, 2015. https://www.research.manchester.ac.uk/portal/en/theses/towards-a-fictionalist-philosophy-of-mathematics(e078d675-7f4c-45e7-a1a0-baf8d899940d).html.
Full textGonzález, del Solar Sarría Rafael. "Mechanismic explanation in ecology." Doctoral thesis, Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona, 2016. http://hdl.handle.net/10803/381073.
Full textEcology is a science of practical and theoretical importance that has recently begun to appeal to professional philosophers. Yet, work on the philosophical foundations of ecology, particularly on its explanatory practices, is still scarce, even though ecologists perceive the debate on ecological explanation as an important one. In this dissertation, I contrast the main theses of three different philosophical projects that attempt to account for scientific explanation in terms of mechanisms descriptions with two cases of ecological explanation based on mechanisms, as ecologists understand the term: the mechanisms of ecological facilitation and competition. The examples I study come from the subfield of ecological succession, though both facilitation and competition are widespread along the whole of ecology. Based on my analysis of those cases I argue that those projects have contributed important elements to the ontology and epistemology of scientific explanation, but that there is still room for improvement towards an adequate characterization of the precise nature of ecological mechanisms and mechanismic explanation in ecology. Following the lead of previous work by systemist philosopher Mario Bunge, I suggest that ecological mechanisms are specific processes in systems, and that, even though they may take different forms, mechanismic explanations consist in descriptions of those processes in the context of a description of the system of interest.
Nebel, Jonathan. "A puzzle about economic explanation: examining the Cournot and Bertrand models of duopoly competition." Kansas State University, 2015. http://hdl.handle.net/2097/18964.
Full textDepartment of Economics
Peri da Silva
Economists use various models to explain why it is that firms are capable of pricing above marginal cost. In this paper, we will examine two of them: the Cournot and Bertrand duopoly models. Economists generally accept both models as good explanations of the phenomenon, but the two models contradict each other in various important ways. The puzzle is that two inconsistent explanations are both regarded as good explanations for the same phenomenon. This becomes especially worrisome when the two models are offering divergent policy recommendations. This report presents that puzzle by laying out how the two models contradict each other in a myriad of ways and then offers five possible solutions to that puzzle from various economists, philosophers of science, and philosophers of economics.
Rossi, Francesca Micol. "Explaining cognitive behaviour : a neurocomputational perspective." Thesis, University of Edinburgh, 2014. http://hdl.handle.net/1842/9739.
Full textHall, Brayton Bruno. "A Language-Game Justification for Narrative in Historical Explanation." Thesis, Virginia Tech, 2017. http://hdl.handle.net/10919/78239.
Full textMaster of Arts
Oshiro, Erika. "A Historical Approach to Understanding Explanatory Proofs Based on Mathematical Practices." Scholar Commons, 2019. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/7882.
Full textRENFRO, MARL K. "TEMPERAMENTS: A CRITIQUE OF EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY." University of Cincinnati / OhioLINK, 2002. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc_num=ucin1022853045.
Full textAppley, Bryan C. "Inference to the best explanation and the challenge of skepticism." Diss., University of Iowa, 2016. https://ir.uiowa.edu/etd/3041.
Full textKwek, Adrian. "Three Studies in the Theory of Function." Thesis, Harvard University, 2012. http://dissertations.umi.com/gsas.harvard:10446.
Full textPhilosophy
James, Rick Davy. "The Argument from Beauty| An Inference to the Best Explanation for the Properties and Phenomenon of Beauty." Thesis, Southeastern Baptist Theological Seminary, 2018. http://pqdtopen.proquest.com/#viewpdf?dispub=13419356.
Full textIn Chapter One, an historical survey will provide a history of beauty as natural theology, beginning with Plato and extending to the mid-twentieth century. This historical research should provide context critical to the development of the argument.
In Chapter Two, the contemporary argument from beauty will be surveyed, but unlike Chapter One, analysis will be through depth and not in breadth. Two contemporary arguments from beauty will be exposited and evaluated: C. S. Lewis’s argument from the aesthetic experience of longing, and the fine-tuning argument of Robin Collins, in which he argues for objective beauty in the universe, with God as the first-cause. Following the analysis of both arguments, there will be a general evaluative summary giving perspective on the combined research of chapters one and two and identifying key elements to be incorporated into the argument from beauty as it is developed.
In Chapter Three, focus will turn to structural elements of the argument. Here, the structure and rationale of abductive arguments will be explained, and the elements of an Inference to the Best Explanation will be delineated. Finally, the criteria that will determine the best explanation will be established, and an outline given that will forecast the argument to follow.
In Chapter Four, descriptive clarity will be given to the two hypotheses and the facts of beauty that require an explanation. First, the two explanatory hypotheses, theism and philosophical naturalism, will be plainly set out. In this context, the various evolutionary accounts of beauty that constitute philosophical naturalism will be explained. These include: natural selection, sexual selection, biophilia hypothesis, null theory, spandrel hypothesis, and social cohesion. Second, the facts of beauty will be identified, categorized, and adumbrated. The facts of beauty that will be explored are: cosmological facts, moral facts, existential facts, epistemological facts, and axiological facts.
In Chapter Five, the explanations of theism and philosophical naturalism will be elaborated and evaluated. This preliminary evaluation will set the stage for the final evaluation. After considering the explanations for each of the facts of beauty, the final evaluation will involve the inference to the best explanation based upon the explanatory criteria.
Chapter Six will be a review of the research, a summary of the argument, and a reiteration of theism as the best explanation for beauty. Lastly, general consideration will be given to possible directions for future research and arguments from beauty.
Pearlberg, Daniel. "Causation, Mechanism and Mind." The Ohio State University, 2015. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc_num=osu1430829433.
Full textSeminara, Simone Giuseppe. "Matter and Explanation. On Aristotle's Metaphysics Book H." Phd thesis, Ecole normale supérieure de lyon - ENS LYON, 2014. http://tel.archives-ouvertes.fr/tel-01061421.
Full textJOHNSON, GREGORY S. "ON THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN PSYCHOLOGY AND NEUROBIOLOGY: LEVELS IN THE COGNITIVE AND BIOLOGICAL SCIENCES." University of Cincinnati / OhioLINK, 2007. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc_num=ucin1178290821.
Full textRoss, Barry. "A fundamental explanation of musical meaning in terms of mental states." Thesis, Stellenbosch : University of Stellenbosch, 2010. http://hdl.handle.net/10019.1/5429.
Full textENGLISH ABSTRACT: This study concerns the widespread phenomenon that music is perceived as meaningful to the listener in some sense. The study adopts a style of conceptual clarification and investigation that is current in the analytic philosophy of language, and is further informed by recent research into the fundamental biology of human musicality, which suggests that musicality and language are neurologically related. The problem of musical meaning is approached as a problem of communicative behaviour, and is hence conceptually related to the concept of meaningfulness in the various modalities of linguistic communication. ‘Communication’ is defined in terms of the intended consequences of communicative acts – that is, a communicative act is an attempt on the behalf of the utterer to cause some sort of change in the listener’s mental states. From this premise, meaning in both musical and linguistic acts is defined in terms the mental states elicited in the mind of the listener. Two classes of mental state are identified: cognitive states, which are propositional in nature; and affective states, which are essentially nonpropositional. It is proposed that meaning in both music and language (as well as in other communicative acts) can be explained in terms of the elicitation of these classes of mental states in the minds of competent listeners, and that in any linguistic or musical act, a competent listener will entertain a composite of these mental states that will be perceived as meaning. The mechanisms responsible for the elicitation of these states are discussed, and it is concluded that the causal powers of the communicative act, as it is represented in the mind, are responsible for the elicitation of these mental states. Directly causal means are responsible for affective states: there is a relationship of direct causation between relevant features of the communicative act, as represented in the mind, and affective states. Affective states are nonpropositional, in that they cannot be subjected to deductive or propositional operations in the mind. By virtue of their being non-propositional, such states are also considered to be beyond verbal explication (‘ineffable’). Cognitive states, on the other hand, are propositional in nature. The mechanisms by which they are realised are complex in terms of propositional computation: the relevant propositional features of the communicative act, as represented in the mind of the listener, undergo manipulation by mental processes (for instance, the computational system for linguistic syntax). Cognitive states are expressible in propositional terms, and are hence expressible in language. Whereas linguistic communication is efficacious for the elicitation of cognitive states, musical utterances tend to elicit affective states to a far greater degree. Furthermore, whereas the syntax of language aids communication in the facilitation of semantics, the syntactic dimension of music is principally a means of implementing affective states in the listener. Therefore, any explanation of musical meaning must take the syntactical dimension of music into account. It is also argued that there are features of performance common to both language (in its spoken modality) and musical utterances that serve to elicit affective states.
AFRIKAANSE OPSOMMING: Hierdie studie ondersoek die verskynsel dat musiek deur die meeste luisteraars as betekenisvol ervaar word. ’n Styl van konseptuele verduideliking en ondersoek word gebruik wat eie is aan die analitiese filosofie van taal. Terselfdertyd word die jongste navorsing op die gebied van die fundamentele biologie van menslike musikaliteit in aanmerking geneem, wat suggereer dat taal en musikale vermoë neurologies met mekaar verwant is. Die probleem van betekenis in musiek word as ʼn probleem van kommunikatiewe gedrag benader, en is dus konseptueel verbind aan die konsep van betekenisvolheid in die verskeie modaliteite van kommunikasie deur middel van taal. ‘Kommunikasie’ word in terme van die geïntendeerde uitkomste van kommunikatiewe aksies/dade gedefinieer. Met ander woorde, ʼn kommunikatiewe aksie/daad is ʼn poging deur die spreker om uiteindelik ʼn verandering in die geestesgesteldheid (‘mental state’) van die luisteraar teweeg te bring. Op hierdie basis word twee tipes geestesgesteldheid onderskei: ʼn kognitiewe gesteldheid, wat proposisioneel van aard is, en ʼn affektiewe gesteldheid, wat nie-proposisioneel is. Daar word voorgestel dat betekenis in beide musiek en taal, soos ook in ander vorme van kommunikasie, verduidelik kan word as die belewenis van sodanige geestesgesteldhede aan die kant van die bedrewe luisteraar. Dit impliseer dat die betekenis van enige uiting in taal of musiek as ʼn bepaalde kombinasie van hierdie twee geestesgesteldhede deur die bedrewe luisteraar ervaar word. Die meganismes wat hierdie geestesgesteldhede ontlok word bespreek, en die gevolgtrekking word gemaak dat dit die kousale mag van die kommunikatiewe daad is, soos dit in die bewussyn (‘mind’) neerslag vind, wat hierdie twee tipes geestesgesteldheid ontlok. Daar word beweer dat ʼn proses van direkte kousaliteit verantwoordelik is vir ʼn affektiewe gesteldheid: daar is ’n oorsaaklike verhouding tussen die onderskeie kenmerke van die kommunikatiewe daad, soos dit in die bewussyn voorgestel word, en die uiteindelike affektiewe geestesgesteldheid. ʼn Affektiewe geestesgesteldheid is nie-proposisioneel omdat dit nie in terme van deduktiewe of proposisionele prosesse in die bewussyn verstaan kan word nie. Omdat dit nie-proposisioneel is word die kenmerke van hierdie affektiewe geestesgesteldheid as onsegbaar (‘ineffable’) deur die luisteraar beleef. Daarteenoor is ʼn kognitiewe geestesgesteldheid proposisioneel van aard. Die meganismes wat veroorsaak dat hierdie geestesgesteldheid gerealiseer word is kompleks: die onderskeie kenmerke van die kommunikatiewe daad, soos dit in die bewussyn van die luisteraar voorgestel word, ondergaan manipulasie deur denkprosesse wat proposisioneel van aard is (bv., die denkproses wat die sintaktiese dimensie van taal moet verwerk). ʼn Kognitiewe geestesgesteldheid kan in proposisionele terme weergegee en gevolglik in taal verwoord word. Terwyl kommunikasie deur middel van taal effektief is om ʼn kognitiewe geestesgesteldheid te ontlok, is musikale uitdrukking veel eerder geskik om ʼn affektiewe geestesgesteldheid te ontlok. Verder, terwyl die sintaksis van taal bydra tot verwesenliking van semantiese betekenis, dra die sintaktiese dimensie van musiek eerder daartoe by om ʼn affektiewe geestesgesteldheid by die luisteraar te vestig. Dus moet elke verduideliking van musikale betekenis die sintaktiese dimensie van musiek in aanmerking neem. Verder word beweer dat daar algemene kenmerke in sowel taal (in die gesproke modaliteit) as musiek voorkom wat spesifiek ʼn affektiewe geestesgesteldheid tot stand bring.
PASLARU, VIOREL. "ECOLOGICAL MECHANISMS IN PHILOSOPHICAL FOCUS." University of Cincinnati / OhioLINK, 2007. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc_num=ucin1195862599.
Full textSarihan, Isik. "Mental Content And Mentalistic Causal Explanation: A Case Against Externalism." Master's thesis, METU, 2011. http://etd.lib.metu.edu.tr/upload/12612726/index.pdf.
Full texts mental states (such as brain states) and certain things that exist outside those realizers (such as what the content of a mental state corresponds to in the actual world.) After clarifications regarding the term &ldquo
externalism&rdquo
and reviewing the history and the various forms of the externalist theory, it is argued that the properties offered by externalist theories as mental properties have no causal influence on behavior, and therefore cannot causally explain it. The argument is largely based on a method of comparing the causal powers of entities which are identical in all respects except their mental properties (as construed by externalism), and the conclusions are supported by metaphysical reflections on causation, dispositions, relational properties and historical properties. Objections to the defended view are considered and refuted. The thesis is written in the style of modern analytic philosophy.