To see the other types of publications on this topic, follow the link: Objectivism.

Journal articles on the topic 'Objectivism'

Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles

Select a source type:

Consult the top 50 journal articles for your research on the topic 'Objectivism.'

Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.

You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.

Browse journal articles on a wide variety of disciplines and organise your bibliography correctly.

1

Parrish, Stephen E. "God and Objectivism: A Critique of Objectivist Philosophy of Religion." Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 8, no. 2 (2007): 169–210. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/41551399.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract Objectivism is committed to atheism. However, Objectivists have done little work in Philosophy of Religion. This article argues that much of the work that they have done is fallacious. In particular, the critique of God that Peikoff gives in Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand is deeply flawed. If they want to justify their atheism, Objectivists need to rework and revise their arguments; in the final analysis, however, it is doubtful that their efforts will succeed.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Parrish, Stephen E. "God and Objectivism: A Critique of Objectivist Philosophy of Religion." Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 8, no. 2 (2007): 169–210. http://dx.doi.org/10.5325/jaynrandstud.8.2.0169.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract Objectivism is committed to atheism. However, Objectivists have done little work in Philosophy of Religion. This article argues that much of the work that they have done is fallacious. In particular, the critique of God that Peikoff gives in Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand is deeply flawed. If they want to justify their atheism, Objectivists need to rework and revise their arguments; in the final analysis, however, it is doubtful that their efforts will succeed.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Dent, Eric B. "Objectivism and Christianity." Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 11, no. 2 (December 1, 2011): 189–213. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/41560411.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract The two primary philosophies upholding reason today are Objectivism and Christianity. They may seem like strange bedfellows, but many of the large perceived gaps between them disappear upon close inspection. This paper analyzes five areas (creation; tabula rasa; life as the ultimate standard; romantic love, sex and marriage; and altruism and the trader principle) in which Objectivist philosophy can be enhanced by assuming Christian philosophical axioms. The argument focuses on Christianity as a philosophy and intentionally does not assume a transcendent God. In each case, the Christian philosophical axioms are more realistic and better supported empirically than the Objectivist axioms.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Dent, Eric B. "Objectivism and Christianity." Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 11, no. 2 (December 1, 2011): 189–213. http://dx.doi.org/10.5325/jaynrandstud.11.2.0189.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract The two primary philosophies upholding reason today are Objectivism and Christianity. They may seem like strange bedfellows, but many of the large perceived gaps between them disappear upon close inspection. This paper analyzes five areas (creation; tabula rasa; life as the ultimate standard; romantic love, sex and marriage; and altruism and the trader principle) in which Objectivist philosophy can be enhanced by assuming Christian philosophical axioms. The argument focuses on Christianity as a philosophy and intentionally does not assume a transcendent God. In each case, the Christian philosophical axioms are more realistic and better supported empirically than the Objectivist axioms.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Goldman, Michael. "Capitalism, Socialism, Objectivism." Philosophy Research Archives 12 (1986): 143–54. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/pra1986/19871221.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Venturinha, Nuno. "Context-Sensitive Objectivism." Logos & Episteme 11, no. 4 (2020): 481–94. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/logos-episteme202011436.

Full text
Abstract:
This paper outlines the major topics addressed in my book Description of Situations: An Essay in Contextualist Epistemology (Springer, 2018), anticipates some possible misunderstandings and discusses issues that warrant further investigation.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

PENDLEBURY, MICHAEL. "OBJECTIVISM VERSUS REALISM." Philosophical Forum 42, no. 1 (February 7, 2011): 79–104. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9191.2010.00379.x.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Harrington, Austin. "Objectivism in Hermeneutics?" Philosophy of the Social Sciences 30, no. 4 (December 2000): 491–507. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/004839310003000401.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Edelman, Christopher. "Montaigne's Moral Objectivism." Philosophy and Literature 35, no. 1 (2011): 32–50. http://dx.doi.org/10.1353/phl.2011.0001.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Yarusso, Lowell. "Constructivism vs. objectivism." Performance + Instruction 31, no. 4 (April 1992): 7–9. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/pfi.4170310404.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
11

Björnsson, Gunnar. "Do ‘Objectivist’ Features of Moral Discourse and Thinking Support Moral Objectivism?" Journal of Ethics 16, no. 4 (June 12, 2012): 367–93. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10892-012-9131-9.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
12

Ommen, Thomas B. "Relativism, Objectivism, and Theology." Horizons 13, no. 2 (1986): 291–305. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0360966900036343.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractRelativism is a central issue in anthropology, philosophy of science, and a number of other disciplines. It is usually contrasted with objectivism or foundationalism, the quest for universal and absolute norms. Richard Bernstein has recently written an illuminating overview of the relativist-objectivist tension and has sketched out a notion of rationality “beyond objectivism and relativism.” This paper is an effort to follow Bernstein's lead and consider the theological implications of objectivism and relativism and the attempt to move beyond them. The first two parts of the paper take up objectivism and relativism in their philosophical and theological forms. The third section briefly explores some aspects of a non-relativist and non-objectivist model of rationality.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
13

Warren C. Gibson. "Modern Physics versus Objectivism." Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 13, no. 2 (2013): 140. http://dx.doi.org/10.5325/jaynrandstud.13.2.0140.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
14

Kang, In ae. "Objectivism' Challenges to Constructivism." Journal of Educational Technology 13, no. 1 (October 30, 1997): 3–19. http://dx.doi.org/10.17232/kset.13.1.3.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
15

Gowans, Christopher W. "Beyond Objectivism and Relativism." International Philosophical Quarterly 25, no. 2 (1985): 207–11. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/ipq19852528.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
16

Lambek, Michael. "Introduction: Treading Beyond Objectivism." Culture 11, no. 1-2 (December 15, 2021): 3–14. http://dx.doi.org/10.7202/1084470ar.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
17

Laurier, Daniel. "Between Phenomenalism and Objectivism." Journal of Philosophical Research 30 (2005): 189–214. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/jpr20053034.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
18

McLaughlin, Andrew. "Beyond Objectivism and Relativism." Philosophical Inquiry 7, no. 1 (1985): 60–63. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/philinquiry19857117.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
19

McKinney, Ronald H. "Beyond Objectivism and Relativism." Modern Schoolman 64, no. 2 (1987): 97–110. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/schoolman198764218.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
20

Margolis, Joseph. "X—Objectivism and Relativism." Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 85, no. 1 (June 1, 1985): 171–92. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/85.1.171.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
21

Fuller, Steve. "Towards objectivism and relativism∗." Social Epistemology 1, no. 4 (October 1987): 351–61. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02691728708578452.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
22

Stige, Brynjulf. "Beyond Objectivism and Relativism?" Nordic Journal of Music Therapy 10, no. 1 (January 2001): 2. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/08098130109478011.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
23

WEINTRAUB, RUTH. "Objectivism without objective probabilities." Theoria 56, no. 1-2 (February 11, 2008): 23–41. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1755-2567.1990.tb00216.x.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
24

Dallmayr, Fred R. "Beyond Objectivism and Relativism." New Vico Studies 3 (1985): 215–19. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/newvico1985339.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
25

Cairns, Dorion, Lester Embree, Fred Kersten, and Richard M. Zaner. "Husserlian Phenomenology and Objectivism." Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 38, no. 2 (January 2007): 116–27. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00071773.2007.11006607.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
26

Rosati, Connie S. "OBJECTIVISM AND RELATIONAL GOOD." Social Philosophy and Policy 25, no. 1 (December 20, 2007): 314–49. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0265052508080126.

Full text
Abstract:
In his critique of egoism as a doctrine of ends, G. E. Moore famously challenges the idea that something can be “good for” someone. Donald Regan has recently revived and developed the Moorean challenge, making explicit its implications for the very idea of individual welfare. If the Moorean is right, there is no distinct, normative property good for, and so no plausible objectivism about ethics could be welfarist. In this essay, I undertake to address the Moorean challenge, clarifying our theoretical alternatives so that we may better decide what to admit into our moral ontology and better assess what may be at stake in whether objectivists treat good or good for (or neither) as fundamental. I compare the Moorean and welfarist pictures of value, providing an account of the form and function of good for. According to this account “good for” expresses a distinct relational value that has its source in the value of persons. Good for value is thus a form of extrinsic value that provides agent-neutral reasons for action, and it plays a pervasive normative role in regulating child rearing, guiding individual life choices, and shaping social policy formation.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
27

Averill, Edward Wilson. "A limited objectivism defended." Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15, no. 1 (March 1992): 27–28. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0140525x00067261.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
28

HAMATI-ATAYA, INANNA. "Transcending objectivism, subjectivism, and the knowledge in-between: the subject in/of ‘strong reflexivity’." Review of International Studies 40, no. 1 (April 23, 2013): 153–75. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0260210513000041.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractThis article addresses theproblématiqueof the subject and the subject-object dichotomy from a post-objectivist, reflexivist perspective informed by a ‘strong’ version of reflexivity. It clarifies the rationale and epistemic-ontological requirements of strong reflexivity comparatively, through a discussion of autoethnography and autobiography, taken as representatives of other variants of reflexive scholarship. By deconstructing the ontological, epistemic, and reflexive statuses of the subject in the auto-ethnographic and auto-biographical variants, the article shows that the move from objectivism to post-objectivism can entail different reconfigurations of the subject-object relation, some of which can lead to subjectivism or an implicit positivist view of the subject. Strong reflexivity provides a coherent and empowering critique of objectivism because it consistently turns the ontological fact of the social situatedness of knowledge into an epistemic principle of social-scientific research, thereby providing reflexivist scholars with a critique of objectivism from within that allows them to reclaim the philosophical, social, and ethical dimensions of objectivity rather than surrender them to the dominant neopositivist tradition.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
29

Vrhovski, Jan. "Shadowlands of Objectivism and Comprehensiveness." Asian Studies 9, no. 1 (January 8, 2021): 227–62. http://dx.doi.org/10.4312/as.2021.9.1.227-262.

Full text
Abstract:
The article aims at presenting an overview of the main concepts in the philosophical thought of Zhang Shenfu, one of the leading intellectuals from Republican China (1912–1949). The study sets out from a brief summary of Zhang’s intellectual achievements, and proceeds by offering a more concise picture of the main influences, developmental stages and finally also central ideas of Zhang’s thought. By offering a general view on the concrete confluences and dissonances between the keystones of Zhang’s philosophy on one side, and its alleged sources in Western and Chinese philosophy on the other, this study further aims at presenting a new insight into the unique characteristics of Zhang’s philosophy. At the same time, by setting the discussion on Zhang’s philosophy in a broader context of contemporary intellectual discourse, the article also endeavours to establish a tentative basis for the future critical analyses and potential revaluations of Zhang Shenfu’s role in intellectual history of modern China.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
30

Vrhovski, Jan. "Shadowlands of Objectivism and Comprehensiveness." Asian Studies 9, no. 1 (January 8, 2021): 227–62. http://dx.doi.org/10.4312/as.2021.9.1.227-262.

Full text
Abstract:
The article aims at presenting an overview of the main concepts in the philosophical thought of Zhang Shenfu, one of the leading intellectuals from Republican China (1912–1949). The study sets out from a brief summary of Zhang’s intellectual achievements, and proceeds by offering a more concise picture of the main influences, developmental stages and finally also central ideas of Zhang’s thought. By offering a general view on the concrete confluences and dissonances between the keystones of Zhang’s philosophy on one side, and its alleged sources in Western and Chinese philosophy on the other, this study further aims at presenting a new insight into the unique characteristics of Zhang’s philosophy. At the same time, by setting the discussion on Zhang’s philosophy in a broader context of contemporary intellectual discourse, the article also endeavours to establish a tentative basis for the future critical analyses and potential revaluations of Zhang Shenfu’s role in intellectual history of modern China.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
31

Margolis, Joseph. "Relativism vs. Pluralism and Objectivism." Journal of Philosophical Research 21 (1996): 95–106. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/jpr_1996_18.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
32

Eggerman, Richard. "TWO KINDS OF VALUATIONAL OBJECTIVISM." Southwest Philosophy Review 10, no. 2 (1994): 167–71. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/swphilreview199410234.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
33

Mason, Elinor. "Objectivism and Prospectivism About Rightness." Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 7, no. 2 (June 5, 2017): 1–22. http://dx.doi.org/10.26556/jesp.v7i2.72.

Full text
Abstract:
In this paper I present a new argument for prospectivism: the view that, for a consequentialist, rightness depends on what is prospectively best rather than what would actually be best. Prospective bestness depends on the agent’s epistemic position, though exactly how that works is not straightforward. I clarify various possible versions of prospectivism, which differ in how far they go in relativizing to the agent’s limitations. My argument for prospectivism is an argument for moderately objective prospectivism, according to which the right thing to do is what would make sense given reasonable beliefs, reasonable probability estimates and a reasonable understanding of value. My argument is an argument for this form of prospectivism over objectivism. Arguments about prospectivism and objectivism usually use an example with the following form: an agent has a choice between options – one she knows would be acceptable, while the other could either be catastrophic or very good. Objectivists argue that the right thing to do is what would in fact be best (though the agent cannot know which option that is) while prospectivists argue that the agent’s ignorance is relevant, and the right thing to do is to compromise. The question is how we should understand the underlying argument. It is not about action guidance. Moderately objective prospectivism is not action guiding, because an actual agent may not have access to reasonable beliefs, probability estimates and so on. Another common argument is that the objective notion is the primary one. I show that there are no good grounds for this claim. My argument uses the distinction between rightness and goodness to show that a consequentialist theory, that bases rightness on goodness, should take into account how much goodness is at stake. Crucially, potential losses as well as gains are relevant. So long as goodness, rather than rightness, is in the driving seat, we should not be “bestness fetishists.” As the name suggest, this would be an irrational privileging of the best option. This argument does not apply to pure deontology: a pure deontology does not use the notion of goodness at all, and so there is nothing to compromise with. If the agent does not know what is right, there is nothing further to say. I end by arguing against a recent strategy that aims to show that although objectivism is true (the right option is the best one), we should sometimes do what is wrong (i.e. what is prospectively best). I argue that insofar as this is correct, it is simply prospectivism with awkward terminology.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
34

Mizrahi, Vivian. "Color Objectivism and Color Pluralism." dialectica 60, no. 3 (September 2006): 283–306. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1746-8361.2006.01070.x.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
35

Nees, Dan, Valerie E. Green, and Kim Treadway. "Activism, Objectivism, and Environmental Politics." Environmental Ethics 25, no. 3 (2003): 295–312. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/enviroethics200325320.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
36

Elkind, David. "Response to Objectivism and Education." Educational Forum 69, no. 4 (December 31, 2005): 328–34. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00131720508984706.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
37

Dorfman, Eran. "Naturalism, Objectivism and Everyday Life." Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 72 (April 3, 2013): 117–33. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1358246113000088.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractIn this paper I analyse the role of naturalism and objectivism in everyday life according to Husserl and Merleau-Ponty. Whereas Husserl attributes the naturalistic attitude mainly to science, he defines the objectivist attitude as a naiveté which equally applies to the natural attitude of everyday life. I analyse the relationship between the natural attitude and lived experience and show Husserl's hesitation regarding the task of phenomenology in describing the lived experience of everyday life, since he considers this experience to be too objectivistic. I use Merleau-Ponty's work to argue that objectivism is an essential characteristic of lived experience and that phenomenology should therefore find ways to integrate it into its descriptions while simultaneously suggesting ways to overcome its rigidity in order to renew perception. I finally propose that the project of the naturalisation of phenomenology could be one of the ways to connect lived experience to the objectivism of everyday life.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
38

Levine, Joseph. "Objectivism-subjectivim: A false dilemma?" Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15, no. 1 (March 1992): 42–43. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0140525x00067431.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
39

Averill, Edward Wilson, and Allan Hazlett. "Color objectivism and color projectivism." Philosophical Psychology 24, no. 6 (June 6, 2011): 751–65. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2011.562645.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
40

Beebe, James R., and David Sackris. "Moral objectivism across the lifespan." Philosophical Psychology 29, no. 6 (April 22, 2016): 912–29. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2016.1174843.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
41

Majka, Wojciech. "A critique of scientific objectivism." International Journal of Academic Research 5, no. 3 (May 23, 2013): 167–75. http://dx.doi.org/10.7813/2075-4124.2013/5-3/b.26.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
42

Dedrick, Don. "Objectivism and the Evolutionary Value of Colour Vision." Dialogue 34, no. 1 (1995): 35–44. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0012217300049283.

Full text
Abstract:
In Color for Philosophers, C. L. Hardin argues that chromatic objectivism—a view that identifies colour with some or other property of objects—must be false. The upshot of Hardin's argument is this: there is, in fact, no principled correlation between physical properties and perceived colours. Since that correlation is a minimal condition for objectivism, objectivism is false. Mohan Matthen, who accepts Hardin's conclusion for what can be called “simple objectivism,” takes it that an adaptationist theory of biological function applied to colour is able to surmount the problems Hardin describes. It is Matthen's view that I am primarily concerned with in this paper. I will argue that it entails an overly simple view of adaptive value—as, perhaps, do all objectivist views.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
43

Hedden, Brian. "A defense of objectivism about evidential support." Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45, no. 5-6 (December 2015): 716–43. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00455091.2015.1123038.

Full text
Abstract:
Objectivism about evidential support is the thesis that facts about the degree to which a body of evidence supports a hypothesis are objective rather than depending on subjective factors like one’s own language or epistemic values. Objectivism about evidential support is key to defending a synchronic, time-slice-centric conception of epistemic rationality, on which what you ought to believe at a time depends only on what evidence you have at that time, and not on how you were at previous times. Here, I defend a version of objectivism about evidential support on which facts about evidential support are grounded in facts about explanatoriness.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
44

Smith, Holly M. "The Zimmerman-Graham Debate on Objectivism versus Prospectivism." Journal of Moral Philosophy 15, no. 4 (August 11, 2018): 401–14. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/17455243-20180006.

Full text
Abstract:
In Living with Uncertainty Michael Zimmerman argues against the Objective view and for the Prospective view of morality. He claims that the conscientious agent would always choose the act that maximizes projected value, and that this is incompatible with Objectivism. Peter Graham defends Objectivism against Zimmerman’s attack. He argues that a conscientious agent must balance fulfilling obligations against avoiding the worst wrong-doings, and that this stance is consistent with Objectivism and with the agent’s choosing an act she believes to be Objectively wrong. In Ignorance and Moral Obligation Zimmerman argues that Graham’s “Objectivism” is only terminologically distinct from his Prospectivism. I argue that Graham faces a dilemma: if his theory delivers different prescriptions from Zimmerman’s, those prescriptions are implausible. On the other hand, if his theory avoids such implausible recommendations, it now generates exactly the same recommendations as Zimmerman’s theory, and so does not constitute a serious challenge to it.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
45

Raskin, Jonathan D. "Objecting, subjecting, and epistemic diversity." Theory & Psychology 30, no. 3 (June 2020): 394–99. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0959354320914392.

Full text
Abstract:
Held (2020) portrays critical and Indigenous psychologists as subscribing to an epistemological “anti-objectivism” that inhibits their ability to combat oppression. She believes that their anti-objectivism yields a troublesome relativism in which truth is overly context-dependent; what counts as true knowledge for one Indigenous group may not count for another. This commentary explores whether critical and Indigenous psychologists are strict “anti-objectivists,” as Held contends. It also challenges the need for epistemological consistency, while encouraging a shift from “objectivism” and “subjectivism” as essentialized states to “objecting” and “subjecting” as complementary ways to explore and study the world.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
46

Dent, Parnell, and Carraher. "Developing an Instrument to Measure Objectivism." Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 18, no. 1 (2018): 1. http://dx.doi.org/10.5325/jaynrandstud.18.1.0001.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
47

Zhang, Long, John A. Parnell, and Eric B. Dent. "Objectivism In China: A Management Perspective." Academy of Management Proceedings 2016, no. 1 (January 2016): 10313. http://dx.doi.org/10.5465/ambpp.2016.10313abstract.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
48

Pueyo-Ibáñez. "Moral Inquiry Beyond Objectivism and Subjectivism." Journal of Speculative Philosophy 35, no. 2 (2021): 165. http://dx.doi.org/10.5325/jspecphil.35.2.0165.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
49

Potaga, Anna. "The "Logical Objectivism" of Gottlob Frege." Philosophical Inquiry 24, no. 3 (2002): 77–94. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/philinquiry2002243/423.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
50

Meltzer, Edmund S. "A Constructivism and Objectivism: Additional Questions." Educational Forum 70, no. 3 (September 30, 2006): 200–201. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00131720608984896.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
We offer discounts on all premium plans for authors whose works are included in thematic literature selections. Contact us to get a unique promo code!

To the bibliography