Academic literature on the topic 'Metaphysical anthropology'
Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles
Consult the lists of relevant articles, books, theses, conference reports, and other scholarly sources on the topic 'Metaphysical anthropology.'
Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.
You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.
Journal articles on the topic "Metaphysical anthropology"
Misztal, Dawid. "The anthropological consequences of the evolution of empiricism." Hybris 19, no. 4 (December 30, 2012): 75–92. http://dx.doi.org/10.18778/1689-4286.19.04.
Full textShevtsov, Sergii. "Transcendental anthropology and poetry (metaphysical parallels)." Sententiae 6, no. 2 (August 30, 2002): 41–51. http://dx.doi.org/10.31649/sent06.02.041.
Full textMaundrell, Richard. "From Rupert Lodge to Sweat Lodge." Dialogue 34, no. 4 (1995): 747–53. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0012217300011094.
Full textFriauf, V. A. "Logos and Tao: from Metaphysics to Anthropology." Izvestiya of Saratov University. Philosophy. Psychology. Pedagogy 12, no. 4 (2012): 45–49. http://dx.doi.org/10.18500/1819-7671-2012-12-4-45-49.
Full textFaritov, Vyacheslav T. "The will to power in ethnogenesis: Nietzschean motives of Eurasian anthropology." Izvestiya of Saratov University. Philosophy. Psychology. Pedagogy 24, no. 2 (June 21, 2024): 180–85. http://dx.doi.org/10.18500/1819-7671-2024-24-2-180-185.
Full textKristeva, Silviya. "Virtualistic Transcendentalism as a Concept of Systematic Critical Metaphysics. The Pentalogy of Valentin Kanawrow." Filosofiya-Philosophy 33, no. 2 (July 1, 2024): 213–23. http://dx.doi.org/10.53656/phil2024-02-08.
Full textJANI, ANNA. "SPIRITUAL ACTS IN ANTHROPOLOGY. EDITH STEIN’S PHENOMENOLOGICAL PERSPECTIVE." HORIZON / Fenomenologicheskie issledovanija/ STUDIEN ZUR PHÄNOMENOLOGIE / STUDIES IN PHENOMENOLOGY / ÉTUDES PHÉNOMÉNOLOGIQUES 10, no. 2 (2021): 425–40. http://dx.doi.org/10.21638/2226-5260-2021-10-2-425-440.
Full textTyson, David. "Should “The Metaphysics of Man” Be a Sixth Branch of Objectivist Philosophy?" Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 22, no. 1 (July 1, 2022): 136–64. http://dx.doi.org/10.5325/jaynrandstud.22.1.0136.
Full textGrenberg, Jeanine. "Anthropology From a Metaphysical Point of View." Journal of the History of Philosophy 37, no. 1 (1999): 91–115. http://dx.doi.org/10.1353/hph.2008.0961.
Full textCohen, Alix A. "Kant's Concept of Freedom and the Human Sciences." Canadian Journal of Philosophy 39, no. 1 (March 2009): 113–35. http://dx.doi.org/10.1353/cjp.0.0035.
Full textDissertations / Theses on the topic "Metaphysical anthropology"
Dargan, Geoffrey David. "The possible self : an exposition and analysis of metaphysical themes in Kierkegaard's theological anthropology." Thesis, University of Oxford, 2016. https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:939bc331-d3af-4144-8aac-f6fa6be95f0b.
Full textMilne, Douglas J. W., and res cand@acu edu au. "A Religious, Ethical and Philosophical Study of the Human Person in the Context of Biomedical Practices." Australian Catholic University. School of Philosophy, 2006. http://dlibrary.acu.edu.au/digitaltheses/public/adt-acuvp148.26072007.
Full textLagrut, Blandine. "Le réalisme moral d'Elizabeth Anscombe : une philosophie de l'intégrité." Electronic Thesis or Diss., Université de Lorraine, 2024. http://www.theses.fr/2024LORR0107.
Full textFor Elizabeth Anscombe, every effort at goodness is also a quest for truth. Moral vigilance takes the form of a Daimôn reminding each person of the task of examining their life: ‘Perhaps in some way, I can’t see, I may be on a bad path, perhaps I am hopelessly wrong in some essential way*.’ This thesis argues that Anscombe is developing an original type of moral realism centred on the notion of integrity and polarised by one question: how does a person come to grasp, as rigorously as possible, the meaning and gravity of their actions? According to her, three conditions are necessary in order to correctly assess the weight of our actions – they provide the blueprint for our work: we need to know what we are actually doing, we need to have some idea of the necessities of our human nature and, finally, we need to recognise the infinite value of this nature.To know what they are doing, the person must be able to identify the criteria for ‘what counts as a relevant description of an action’. This is precisely what Anscombe sets out to do in her study of intention. She shows that it is possible to isolate types of action which we know that, if we do them intentionally, we are in the wrong. The category of "intrinsically unjust act" becomes available again, providing the starting point for a realist moral epistemology.The person also needs to justify their assessments by basing them on a thorough understanding of the human being. Here again, Anscombe makes a major shift by restoring consistency to the concept of human nature. She relies on the idea that we learn something about the kind of being that humans are by unfolding the logical form of their linguistic practices. Her meta-ethics revolves around an often-unnoticed axis, combining Aristotle’s naturalism and Wittgenstein’s logical grammar.Finally, an action will only be true on a moral level if it manifests the “mystical” value of human nature. Bringing this aspect to light is the most innovative contribution of this thesis. An in-depth study of the ethico-religious texts reveals the core of her metaphysical anthropology: humans are not only rational animals, but also spiritual beings, endowed with a dignity that we can know through “connaturality” or “mystical perception”.By exploring the various facets of Anscombean moral realism, we can ultimately clarify its role in the contemporary ethical debate on absolutism. Are certain acts to be rejected absolutely, whatever the cost to the well-being of the person or the consequent situation? For Anscombe, the answer is yes. But this cannot be done either at the expense of personal discernment or at the cost of alienation. Her way of conceiving the human makes it possible to resolve the tension by establishing that the prohibition does not need to be decreed by an external authority to be absolute. It can be imposed internally on the agent, as compelling evidence, due to their spiritual nature.*G. E. M. Anscombe, ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’ in Ethics, Religion and Politics, Collected Philosophical Pa-pers III, Oxford, Blackwell, 1981, p. 37.Keywords: moral realism, integrity, absolutism, philosophy of action, moral epistemology, meta-ethics, naturalism, logical grammar, mystical perception, connaturality, metaphysical anthropology, spiritual nature
Holdsworth, Christopher John. "The revolution in anthropology : a comparative analysis of the metaphysics of E.B.Tylor (1832-1917) and Bronislaw Malinowski (1884-1942)." Thesis, University of Oxford, 1994. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.240214.
Full textCykowski, Elizabeth. "Summoning the courage for philosophising : a new reading of Heidegger's 'The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics'." Thesis, University of Oxford, 2015. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:8afe3dae-439c-4caa-9046-5e3b94efed61.
Full textDomenech, Théodora. "Phénoménologie et métaphysique dans la pensée de Max Scheler." Thesis, Montpellier 3, 2018. http://www.theses.fr/2018MON30069/document.
Full textMax Scheler’s phenomenological thinking is based on the idea that love is the source of all knowledge. Defined as the ultimate intentional act, love is an essentially personal act. This claim drives the philosopher to consider the existence of an infinite personal God – a loving God - as an eidetic necessity. This raises the following questions: does the essence of God arise from an intuitive experience grounded in love? Or is love conceived as the source of all knowledge according to an existing representation of God defined as love? Taking Scheler’s position on the matter as the guiding thread of my research, I examine the possibility of a phenomenology free from any metaphysical presupposition. To this end, several definitions of the term metaphysics will be examined: ontological realism, idealist subjectivism, and theological Weltanschauung. I first question Scheler’s thought through the prism of the debate surrounding Husserl’s idealist turn by asking whether his personalist phenomenology can be described as « realist » and if so, in what sense. Then I examine all the religious axioms that Scheler uses in his phenomenology to highlight what I call a « theo-logic », i.e. an implicit theological conception of phenomenological logic. Finally, I look at how Scheler criticizes phenomenology in the hope of revealing its implicit metaphysical presuppositions. My thesis thus sheds light on why Scheler, at the end of his life, decided to put phenomenology aside and to define his thinking in terms of a new metaphysics
Jullien, Stanislas. "La finitude infinie et ses figures : considérations philosophiques autour de la radicalisation de la finitude originaire chez Derrida." Thesis, Paris 4, 2014. http://www.theses.fr/2014PA040146.
Full textWe set out to construct a geography of historical aiming to cartograph the site where philosophy reaches its end. In so doing, two main constraints at least have to be taken into account. We first have to describe the site in order to locate it. We argue that the site in question can only be occupied by infinite finitude, for it is our assumption that only infinite finitude holds its inaugural taking-Place, a taking-Place wherein infinite finitude will have to push its creative originarity so far as to release in itself an infinity that will be affected in return by a novel meaning. Secondly, we have to break new ground in textual territories, which will enable us to uncover the system of conceptual coordinates that will make it possible to cartograph the site of infinite finitude. We argue that it is the territory constructed by Derrida that hosts the native cartography of infinite finitude because of the intervention, both inaugural and structural, of infinite finitude on that territory. It follows that, in order to dwell in the articulated unit of these two constraints, we have to maintain a speculative posture in the following cardinal proposition: infinite finitude IS deconstruction. This posture makes it possible to delineate and re-Inscribe infinite finitude on the Derridean territory by (re)constructing a plane of intelligibility through the combination of both the phenomenologico-Transcendental and thanatologico-Trancendental axes on the one hand; by showing, on the other hand, that if infinite finitude confronts the Derridean territory with an aporetic charge operating as a pharmakon, that pharmacology could release novel figures of infinite finitude - hermeneutic (Heidegger), as well as speculative (Hegel), ones
Blanc-brude, Gilles. "Psychologie et anthropologie dans la philosophie de Kant." Thesis, Paris 4, 2010. http://www.theses.fr/2010PA040013.
Full textKant’s philosophy is not a denial of any form of psychology. Despite the uncertainty of the systematic status concerning the mind’s empirical knowledge and the impossibility to use mathematics to bring this knowledge into the scientific field, despite the vacuity of a deduction about the metaphysical properties of the soul made a priori and the pointlessness of a psychological foundation of both philosophy and logic as well as moral, in brief, despite Kant’s antipsychologism and antinaturalism, themes and psychological issues do remain worthwhile and legitimate in his philosophy. The chapter on “Paralogisms” in the Critique of Pure Reason, associated to the “Refutation of Idealism”, does indeed put an end to the psychologia rationalis -which stems from Wolff’s metaphysics- but yet it makes it possible for psychology to be integrated into anthropology while following the leading thread of experience. Kant’s approach of psychology being intimately related to transcendental philosophy will be both its complement and its illustration through a series of considerations on the genesis of our knowledge, on the connection between interiority and exteriority, the various degrees of consciousness and eventually through considerations on the free use of our mental faculties. The first part will deal with the difficulties to set psychology in relation to Kant’s anthropology and philosophy. The second part will set out the main arguments against empirical and rational psychology. The last part will study Kant’s Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View as being the philosophical fulfilment of an untimely theory of the mind complying with the demands of criticism
Mercant, Simó Jaume. "La metafísica del conocimiento de Karl Rahner. Análisis de "Espíritu en el mundo"." Doctoral thesis, Universitat Abat Oliba CEU, 2017. http://hdl.handle.net/10803/462803.
Full textEl teólogo jesuita Karl Rahner, después del Concilio Vaticano II, se convirtió en el paladín de la nouvelle théologie y en el princeps novorum theologorum mediante la proclama de su giro antropológico. Es menester analizar a este teólogo de Friburgo, para comprenderlo adecuadamente, desde sus fundamentos filosóficos. La metafísica trascendental de Karl Rahner ―expresada en su célebre obra Geist in Welt― está claramente fundamentada en el pensamiento del existencialista Heidegger y en el tomismo trascendental de Maréchal. No obstante, Rahner se presenta como auténtico intérprete de santo Tomás de Aquino, mas, en verdad, tergiversa los mismos textos, contextos y principios del Angélico. Nuestro autor, con su Erkenntnismetaphysik, lleva el cogito cartesiano hasta sus últimas consecuencias, identificando en el hombre el ser, el conocer y el objeto conocido, ignorando la distinción que el Angélico hace del ser natural y del ser cognoscitivo. Por otra parte, el concepto clave, para entender la metafísica trascendental del padre Rahner, es el Vorgriff o anticipación, que es un saber apriórico y atemático del ser en general. Además, Karl Rahner llega a mal interpretar la gnoseología del Aquinate identificando ―sic et simpliciter― la conversio ad phantasma, la abstractio y la reditio in seipsum, sin tener en cuenta que santo Tomás habla de una unidad de los distintos procesos cognoscitivos, pero no los identifica. Por consiguiente, Karl Rahner instrumentaliza la metafísica y la gnoseología tomistas prácticamente en su totalidad. En definitiva ―siguiendo a Cornelio Fabro―, Rahner “non tam est thomista, quam philosophiae thomisticae depravator”.
The Jesuit theologian Karl Rahner, after the Second Vatican Council, became the nouvelle théologie's paladin and princeps novorum theologorum by making an anthropological turn. It is necessary to analyze this theologian from Freiburg from his philosophical foundations to properly understand him. Karl Rahner's transcendental metaphysic ―expressed in his famous work Geist in Welt― is clearly based on both Heidegger's existential thought and Maréchal’s transcendental Thomism. Nevertheless, although Rahner acts as an authentic Saint Thomas of Aquinas interpreter, he distorts Angelic's texts, contexts and principles. Our author, with his Erkenntnismetaphysik, takes the Cartesian cogito to the last consequences, identifying in man the being, knowledge and known object, ignoring the distinction that Angelic makes between natural being and cognitive being. Additionally, the key concept to understand Father Rahner's transcendental metaphysics is Vorgriff or anticipation, which is an aprioric and unthematic knowledge of the being in general. Furthermore, Karl Rahner misunderstands Aquinas’ gnoseology, identifying ―sic et simpliciter― the conversio ad phantasma, abstractio and reditio in seipsum, disregarding that Saint Thomas refers to a unity between different cognitive processes without identifying them. Consequently, Karl Rahner instrumentalizes thomistic metaphysics and gnoseology, almost in its entirety. In short ―as Cornelio Fabro indicates― Rahner “non tam est thomista, quam philosophiae thomisticae depravator”.
Brown, Julius. "Penser le corps, sa puissance et sa destinée chez Spinoza : aux sources de son anthropologie." Thesis, Strasbourg, 2015. http://www.theses.fr/2015STRAK012/document.
Full textSpinoza assesses the Copernican revolution and advocates a rationalist and materialistic naturalismagainst the onto-theological tradition, Aristotle and Descartes as the two main figures thereof,theologians and the Bible not to mention. Spinoza interprets the error of geocentrism as indicating twoother errors: classical anthropological dualism which subjugated the body to the soul and the illusion offree-will. By gnoseological, psychophysical and socio-emotional rehabilitation of the body, he claims tolead man to present salvation, not eschatological, reconciling him with himself and with God as Nature.The permanence of Hebraic anthropological sensibility is pregnant, which does not cancel metaphysical,soteriological and ethical disparities between him and the Bible. These disparities could bring Spinozacloser to Aristotle than to Descartes. Will the spinozian project keep its promises without relapsing intothe traps of the mythical and the mystical ?
Books on the topic "Metaphysical anthropology"
Oya, Alberto. The Metaphysical Anthropology of Julián Marías. Cham: Springer Nature Switzerland, 2024. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-61804-8.
Full textTodd, Richard. The Sufi doctrine of man: Ṣadr al-Dī̄n al-Qūnawī's metaphysical anthropology. Leiden: Brill, 2014.
Find full textJean, Grégori. L'humanité à son insu: Phénoménologie, anthropologie, métaphysique. Wuppertal: Association internationale de phénoménologie, 2020.
Find full textEduardo Batalha Viveiros de Castro. Métaphysiques cannibales: Lignes d'anthropologie post-structurale. Paris: Presses universitaires de France, 2009.
Find full textEduardo Batalha Viveiros de Castro. Metafísicas caníbales: Líneas de antropología postestructural. Madrid: Katz, 2010.
Find full textGuz, Tadeusz. Historisch-systematische Beiträge zur Anthropologie. Weilheim-Bierbronnen: Gustav-Siewerth-Akademie, 2000.
Find full textCapelli, Virginia. Essere per avere: Progetto culturale di crescita della persona per l'ordine della convivenza civile nel mondo laico e religioso. Roma: Aracne, 2010.
Find full textVedder, Ben. Mens en metafysica: Mogelijkheid en grens van een metafysisch mensbeeld. Tilburg: Tilburg University Press, 1991.
Find full textGiannini, Gianluca. Condizione umana. Genova: Il melangolo, 2009.
Find full textGonzález, Juan A. García. El ser y la libertad. Málaga: Edinford, 1992.
Find full textBook chapters on the topic "Metaphysical anthropology"
Oya, Alberto. "The Metaphysical Anthropology of Julián Marías." In Palgrave Frontiers in Philosophy of Religion, 23–51. Cham: Springer Nature Switzerland, 2024. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-61804-8_3.
Full textMeyer, Michel. "Toward an Anthropology of Rhetoric." In From Metaphysics to Rhetoric, 111–36. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 1989. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2593-9_9.
Full textLlewelyn, John. "Lévi-Strauss or Ricoeur: Structural or Hermeneutic Anthropology." In Beyond Metaphysics?, 153–70. London: Palgrave Macmillan UK, 1985. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-07558-4_8.
Full textBello, Angela Ales. "The Sense of Things—Hyletics, Anthropology, Metaphysics." In The Sense of Things, 57–76. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2015. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-15395-7_5.
Full textBöhr, Christoph. "Anthropologie und Transzendentalphilosophie: ihre Verschränkung in der Bestimmung des ‚Specificum humanum‘. Zu Richard Schaefflers Antwort auf die Frage nach dem Menschen." In Colloquium Metaphysicum, 97–109. Wiesbaden: Springer Fachmedien Wiesbaden, 2023. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-658-42084-0_8.
Full textBarash, Jeffrey Andrew. "Anthropology, Metaphysics, and the Problem of Historical Meaning in Heidegger’s Interpretation of the Kehre." In Martin Heidegger and the Problem of Historical Meaning, 231–302. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 1988. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-3579-2_7.
Full textGalán Díez, Ilia. "Dialogue with Santob: Reflections on Politics, Sociology, Anthropology, Psychology, Ethics Aesthetics, Metaphysics and Theodicy." In The Birth of Thought in the Spanish Language, 63–72. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-50977-8_11.
Full textCykowski, Beth. "From Life to Spirit." In Heidegger's Metaphysical Abyss, 131–58. Oxford University Press, 2021. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198865407.003.0007.
Full textVoss, Stephen. "Descartes: The End of Anthropology." In Reason, Will, and Sensation, 273–306. Oxford University PressOxford, 1994. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198240839.003.0015.
Full textBANASIAK, DANIEL. "Olga Siedakowa o poezji „głuchych” lat siedemdziesiątych." In Tradycja i nowoczesność. Z zagadnień języka i literatury Słowian Wschodnich 2, 20–31. Wydawnictwo Naukowe Uniwersytetu Pedagogicznego w Krakowie, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.24917/9788380845282.2.
Full textConference papers on the topic "Metaphysical anthropology"
Hadzantonis, Michael. "Becoming Spiritual: Documenting Osing Rituals and Ritualistic Languages in Banyuwangi, Indonesia." In GLOCAL Conference on Asian Linguistic Anthropology 2019. The GLOCAL Unit, SOAS University of London, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.47298/cala2019.17-6.
Full textSvoboda, David. "WHY SHOULD METAPHYSICS BE IMPOSSIBLE?" In SGEM 2014 Scientific SubConference on ANTHROPOLOGY, ARCHAEOLOGY, HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY. Stef92 Technology, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.5593/sgemsocial2014/b31/s11.118.
Full text