Academic literature on the topic 'Gilbarg problem'

Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles

Select a source type:

Consult the lists of relevant articles, books, theses, conference reports, and other scholarly sources on the topic 'Gilbarg problem.'

Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.

You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.

Journal articles on the topic "Gilbarg problem"

1

Schief, W. K., and C. Rogers. "The Da Rios system under a geometric constraint: the Gilbarg problem." Journal of Geometry and Physics 54, no. 3 (July 2005): 286–300. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.geomphys.2004.10.001.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Fernández-Rincón, Sergio, and Julián López-Gómez. "The Singular Perturbation Problem for a Class of Generalized Logistic Equations Under Non-classical Mixed Boundary Conditions." Advanced Nonlinear Studies 19, no. 1 (February 1, 2019): 1–27. http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/ans-2018-2034.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract This paper studies a singular perturbation result for a class of generalized diffusive logistic equations, {d\mathcal{L}u=uh(u,x)} , under non-classical mixed boundary conditions, {\mathcal{B}u=0} on {\partial\Omega} . Most of the precursors of this result dealt with Dirichlet boundary conditions and self-adjoint second order elliptic operators. To overcome the new technical difficulties originated by the generality of the new setting, we have characterized the regularity of {\partial\Omega} through the regularity of the associated conormal projections and conormal distances. This seems to be a new result of a huge relevance on its own. It actually complements some classical findings of Serrin, [39], Gilbarg and Trudinger, [21], Krantz and Parks, [27], Foote, [18] and Li and Nirenberg [28] concerning the regularity of the inner distance function to the boundary.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Volz, M. G., M. Brazil, C. J. Ras, K. J. Swanepoel, and D. A. Thomas. "The Gilbert arborescence problem." Networks 61, no. 3 (July 18, 2012): 238–47. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/net.21475.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

McLoughlin, John Grant. "Solutions to Calendar." Mathematics Teacher 90, no. 4 (April 1997): 298–99. http://dx.doi.org/10.5951/mt.90.4.0298.

Full text
Abstract:
Problems 1–19, 28, and 29 were submitted by Margaret J. Kenney and Stanley J. Bezuszka. S.J. of the Mathematics Institute, Boston College, Chestnut Hill. MA 02167-3809. Problems 20–22 appear in The Wohascum County Problem Book by George T. Gilbert. Mark I. Krusemeyer, and Loren C. Larson Washington, D. C.: Mathematics) Association of America, 1993). Problems 23–27 were prepared by Robert Gerver and hts mathematics-research students, Sharon Poczter, Parisa Golestaneh, Nancy Friedlander, A1exis Soterakis, Nicole Miritello, Laura Henning, and Dalita Balassanian of North Shore High School, Glen Head, NY 11545.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Gnedin, Alexander V., and Denis I. Miretskiy. "Winning Rate in the Full-Information Best-Choice Problem." Journal of Applied Probability 44, no. 02 (June 2007): 560–65. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s002190020000317x.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Gnedin, Alexander V., and Denis I. Miretskiy. "Winning Rate in the Full-Information Best-Choice Problem." Journal of Applied Probability 44, no. 02 (June 2007): 560–65. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0021900200118030.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Gnedin, Alexander V., and Denis I. Miretskiy. "Winning Rate in the Full-Information Best-Choice Problem." Journal of Applied Probability 44, no. 2 (June 2007): 560–65. http://dx.doi.org/10.1239/jap/1183667422.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Bonafini, Mauro, and Édouard Oudet. "A convex approach to the Gilbert–Steiner problem." Interfaces and Free Boundaries 22, no. 2 (July 6, 2020): 131–55. http://dx.doi.org/10.4171/ifb/436.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Samuels, Stephen M. "Why do these quite different best-choice problems have the same solutions?" Advances in Applied Probability 36, no. 02 (June 2004): 398–416. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0001867800013537.

Full text
Abstract:
The full-information best-choice problem, as posed by Gilbert and Mosteller in 1966, asks us to find a stopping rule which maximizes the probability of selecting the largest of a sequence of n i.i.d. standard uniform random variables. Porosiński, in 1987, replaced a fixed n by a random N, uniform on {1,2,…,n} and independent of the observations. A partial-information problem, imbedded in a 1980 paper of Petruccelli, keeps n fixed but allows us to observe only the sequence of ranges (max - min), as well as whether or not the current observation is largest so far. Recently, Porosiński compared the solutions to his and Petruccelli's problems and found that the two problems have identical optimal rules as well as risks that are asymptotically equal. His discovery prompts the question: why? This paper gives a good explanation of the equivalence of the optimal rules. But even under the lens of a planar Poisson process model, it leaves the equivalence of the asymptotic risks as somewhat of a mystery. Meanwhile, two other problems have been shown to have the same limiting risks: the full-information problem with the (suboptimal) Porosiński-Petruccelli stopping rule, and the full-information ‘duration of holding the best’ problem of Ferguson, Hardwick and Tamaki, which turns out to be nothing but the Porosiński problem in disguise.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Samuels, Stephen M. "Why do these quite different best-choice problems have the same solutions?" Advances in Applied Probability 36, no. 2 (June 2004): 398–416. http://dx.doi.org/10.1239/aap/1086957578.

Full text
Abstract:
The full-information best-choice problem, as posed by Gilbert and Mosteller in 1966, asks us to find a stopping rule which maximizes the probability of selecting the largest of a sequence of n i.i.d. standard uniform random variables. Porosiński, in 1987, replaced a fixed n by a random N, uniform on {1,2,…,n} and independent of the observations. A partial-information problem, imbedded in a 1980 paper of Petruccelli, keeps n fixed but allows us to observe only the sequence of ranges (max - min), as well as whether or not the current observation is largest so far. Recently, Porosiński compared the solutions to his and Petruccelli's problems and found that the two problems have identical optimal rules as well as risks that are asymptotically equal. His discovery prompts the question: why? This paper gives a good explanation of the equivalence of the optimal rules. But even under the lens of a planar Poisson process model, it leaves the equivalence of the asymptotic risks as somewhat of a mystery. Meanwhile, two other problems have been shown to have the same limiting risks: the full-information problem with the (suboptimal) Porosiński-Petruccelli stopping rule, and the full-information ‘duration of holding the best’ problem of Ferguson, Hardwick and Tamaki, which turns out to be nothing but the Porosiński problem in disguise.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles

Dissertations / Theses on the topic "Gilbarg problem"

1

Grice, Glenn Noel Mathematics UNSW. "Constant speed flows and the nonlinear Schr??dinger equation." Awarded by:University of New South Wales. Mathematics, 2004. http://handle.unsw.edu.au/1959.4/20509.

Full text
Abstract:
This thesis demonstrates how the geometric connection between the integrable Heisenberg spin equation, the nonlinear Schr??dinger equation and fluid flows with constant velocity magnitude along individual streamlines may be exploited. Specifically, we are able to construct explicitly the complete class of constant speed flows where the constant pressure surfaces constitute surfaces of revolution. This class is undoubtedly important as it contains many of the specific cases discussed earlier by other authors.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Duhem, Ludovic. "L'être préindividuel de l'œuvre d'art : Simondon et le problème de l'esthétique." Lille 3, 2008. http://www.theses.fr/2008LIL30035.

Full text
Abstract:
Cette étude vise à établir le problème de l'esthétique dans la philosophie de Gilbert Simondon (1924-1989). L'ontologie, l'épistémologie et la technologie ont fait l'objet de nombreuses études et publications, mais l'esthétique demeure un aspect sous-estimé, voire totalement ignoré par les commentateurs. Nous voudrions montrer que l'absence d'une doctrine esthétique autonome ne signifie pas qu'aucune réflexion relative au sensible et à l'art n'existe chez Simondon. L'examen de l'ensemble formé par L'individuation à la lumière des notions de forme et d'information et Du mode d'existence des objets techniques montre ainsi d'une part que la critique de l'être comme substance, de l'individu comme composé de matière et de forme, de la connaissance comme rapport du sujet à l'objet, s'applique à tout type de réalité, et donc nécessairement aux êtres esthétiques ; d'autre part, que la réhabilitation de l'objet technique et sa réinscription dans l'évolution du rapport de l'homme au monde permet de sortir la technique de l'utilitarisme et de réévaluer la place de l'esthétique dans la culture. La réforme notionnelle imposée par la philosophie génétique s'avère ainsi d'une grande fécondité pour renouveler la réflexion esthétique, mais elle demeure à construire. Pour y parvenir, il faut résoudre certaines tensions internes à la pensée de Simondon, mais il faut également tenir compte de la dissémination des réflexions esthétiques dans le "corpus secondaire", dont cette étude propose la première exégèse complète. En définitive, cette étude montre que l'esthétique est la tache aveugle de la pensée de Simondon et qu'il est tout à fait légitime d'en opérer une reconstruction critique
This study aims to establish the issue of aesthetics in Gilbert Simondon's philosophy. Ontology, epistemology and technology have been the subject of many studies and publications, but esthetics remains an underestimated aspect, or even totally ignored by commentators. Therefore, we would demonstrate that the absence of an autonomous aesthetic doctrine doesn't mean that no reflexion about the physical world and art exist in Simondon. The examinnation of the whole composed by l'individuation à la lumière des notions de forme et d'information and Du mode d'existence des objets techniques show it clearly by the universality of its concepts. The notional reform lay down by the fundamental philosophic gesture to think reality toward genesis is truly a great way to make a new form of aesthetics, but it stays to rebuild. To make it possible, it is necessary to solve certain intern tensions in Simondon's thought, but it's necessary also to be aware of the dissemination of aesthetics reflexions in the "secondary corpus", studied here for the first time. Definitely, this study reveals that aesthetics is the blind spot of Simondon thought and that is totally legitime to make a critical reconstruction of it
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Lefebvre, Anne. "De la pensée de l'image à l'image de la pensée : la philosophie de Gilbert Simondon A la lumière du problème de l'invention." Lille 3, 2011. http://www.theses.fr/2011LIL30044.

Full text
Abstract:
Cette thèse veut montrer que le problème de l'invention recouvre un enjeu ontologique parfaitement général dans la philosophie de Simondon, quand bien même ce dernier a développé une riche réflexion sur les techniques. Le concept d'invention ne peut être réduit à un concept technologique ; il ne suffit pas de considérer son élargissement au lieu d'une psychologie qui aborderait l'invention dans la pensée sous le seul aspect de l'imagination. ; il serait inapproprié de la faire servir une anthropologie. Quand la notion d'invention est un motif omniprésent dans les deux thèses que Simondon a rédigées en 1958 (L'individuation à a lumière des notions de forme et d'information/Du mode d'existence des objets techniques), seule la théorie du devenir de l'image développée dans le cours Imagination et invention (1965) articule le concept d'invention, et permet de saisir les enjeux pleins et entiers que recouvre ce problème. On doit donc partir de cette théorie qui défait de manière inédite le dualisme de l'âme et du corps, en faisant de l'image, non plus le produit des facultés psychiques, mais ce qui autorise le déphasage de l'activité vitale en activités psychique et somatique. Elle fait de l'acte d'invention la clef du devenir d'une même activité problématique du vivant, en lequel le devenir de la pensée est impliqué. Il est nécesaire alors de procéder à l'éclairage rétrospectif du motif de l'invention dans les deux thèses, indice d'un problème subsistant à leur horizon, et de construire le manifeste rétroactif de la philosophie de Simondon comme philosophie de l'invention, l'acte d'invention constituant le mode de construction problématique même de la pensée philosophique
This thesis intends to show thet the problem of invention has a generalised ontological stake in Simondon's philosophy, within and beyond his rich reflection on technology. The concept of invention cannot be reduced to a technological concept ; its generalisation, in lieu of a psychology that would approach invention in thought, dealing with it within imagination, does not suffice ; it is inappropriate to make this concept subservient to an anthropological approach. While the notion of invention is an omnipresent motif in Simondon's two 1958 thesis (L'individuation à la lumière des notions de forme et d'information/Du mode d'existence des objets technqiues), it is only the theory of the becoming of the image, developed in Imagination et invention (1965) that presents us with a concept of invention, enabling us to grasp the full measure of the stakes inherent in this problem. We thus need to begin from this theory, which proceeds to radically undo the body/soul dualism, resulting in a view of the image, not as product of the psychic faculties, but as that which enables us to think the "déphasage" of vital activity into psychic and somatic activities. This theory makes the act of the invention the key of the problematical becoming of one self-same vital activity, in which the becoming of thought is implicated. This insight obliges us to throw a retrospective light on the motif of invention as it appears in the two thesis, as an index, as an index of a problem that subsists on their horizon, and to construct a retroactive manifesto of Simondon's philosophy, in which the act of invention constitutes the problematical mode of construction of thought itself
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Reigeluth, Tyler. "Comporter la norme. La normativité de l’apprentissage algorithmique à partir du problème du comportement." Doctoral thesis, Universite Libre de Bruxelles, 2018. http://hdl.handle.net/2013/ULB-DIPOT:oai:dipot.ulb.ac.be:2013/264090.

Full text
Abstract:
Cette recherche se donne comme défi de retracer les enjeux normatifs liés au développement du sous-domaine de l’intelligence artificielle appelé machine learning. Bien que celui-ci connaisse un impressionnant regain d’intérêt depuis le début du XXIe siècle, et ce à travers un nombre croissant d’activités sociales, son émergence remonte au moins à la première moitié du XXe siècle. En effet, l’idée de concevoir des machines capables de modéliser l’apprentissage organique est largement concomitante au projet cybernétique de fonder une science du contrôle et de la communication. A force de modéliser l’apprentissage, il devient progressivement possible d’envisager à partir des années 1940 et 50 que les machines elles-mêmes seraient capables d’apprendre. C’est par l’observation des comportements des machines qu’une formalisation algorithmique de l’apprentissage s’impose. A partir de cette mise en scène, nous chercherons à montrer en quoi l’apprentissage algorithmique n’est pas nécessairement une question d’automatisation de l’apprentissage et que le comportement permet, au contraire, de problématiser la normativité des algorithmes apprenants en ce qu’ils participent activement à certaines activités sociales (travail, enseignement, guerre, etc.). Il s’agira, à partir des philosophies de Georges Canguilhem et Gilbert Simondon, de montrer en quoi les effets normatifs induits par l’apprentissage algorithmique, comme mode de gouvernement au sein d’activités sociales données, peuvent se comprendre à l’aune du concept de "répertoire de comportements potentiels".
Doctorat en Philosophie
info:eu-repo/semantics/nonPublished
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Boucher, Denise. "On the concept of a heedful frame of mind in the work of Gilbert Ryle : the problems of its episodic nature and its relation to the issue of voluntariness." Thesis, National Library of Canada = Bibliothèque nationale du Canada, 2000. http://www.collectionscanada.ca/obj/s4/f2/dsk2/ftp01/MQ54269.pdf.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Bernot, Marc. "Transport optimal et irrigation." Phd thesis, École normale supérieure de Cachan - ENS Cachan, 2005. http://tel.archives-ouvertes.fr/tel-00132078.

Full text
Abstract:
L'objet de cette thèse est de modéliser et d'étudier des structures d'irrigation telles les nervures des feuilles, réseau sanguin, poumons,etc. Un modèle généralisant le problème de Gilbert Steiner est introduit ; on étudie alors les propriétés d'existence, de stabilité et régularité. Des algorithmes sont alors proposés pour la simulation.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Holm, Cyril. "F. A. Hayek's Critique of Legislation." Doctoral thesis, Uppsala universitet, Juridiska institutionen, 2014. http://urn.kb.se/resolve?urn=urn:nbn:se:uu:diva-236890.

Full text
Abstract:
The dissertation concerns F. A. Hayek’s (1899–1992) critique of legislation. The purpose of the investigation is to clarify and assess that critique. I argue that there is in Hayek’s work a critique of legislation that is distinct from his well-known critique of social planning. Further that the main claim of this critique is what I refer to as Hayek’s legislation tenet, namely that legislation that aims to achieve specific aggregate results in complex orders of society will decrease the welfare level.           The legislation tenet gains support; (i) from the welfare claim – according to which there is a positive correlation between the utilization of knowledge and the welfare level in society; (ii) from the dispersal of knowledge thesis – according to which the total knowledge of society is dispersed and not available to any one agency; and (iii) from the cultural evolution thesis – according to which evolutionary rules are more favorable to the utilization of knowledge in social cooperation than are legislative rules. More specifically, I argue that these form two lines of argument in support of the legislation tenet. One line of argument is based on the conjunction of the welfare claim and the dispersal of knowledge thesis. I argue that this line of argument is true. The other line of argument is based on the conjunction of the welfare claim and the cultural evolution thesis. I argue that this line of argument is false, mainly because the empirical work of political scientist Elinor Ostrom refutes it. Because the two lines of argument support the legislation tenet independently of each other, I argue that Hayek’s critique of legislation is true. In this dissertation, I further develop a legislative policy tool as based on the welfare claim and Hayek’s conception of coercion. I also consider Hayek’s idea that rules and law are instrumental in forging rational individual action and rational social orders, and turn to review this idea in light of the work of experimental economist Vernon Smith and economic historian Avner Greif. I find that Smith and Greif support this idea of Hayek’s, and I conjecture that it contributes to our understanding of Adam Smith’s notion of the invisible hand: It is rules – not an invisible hand – that prompt subjects to align individual and aggregate rationality in social interaction. Finally, I argue that Hayek’s critique is essentially utilitarian, as it is concerned with the negative welfare consequences of certain forms of legislation. And although it may appear that the dispersal of knowledge thesis will undermine the possibility of carrying out the utilitarian calculus, due to the lack of knowledge of the consequences of one’s actions – and therefore undermine the legislation tenet itself – I argue that the distinction between utilitarianism conceived as a method of deliberation and utilitarianism conceived as a criterion of correctness may be used to save Hayek’s critique from this objection.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Leitão, Antonio C. G. [Verfasser]. "Ein Iterationsverfahren für elliptische Cauchy-Probleme und die Verknüpfung mit der Backus-Gilbert-Methode / von Antonio C. G. Leitão." 1996. http://d-nb.info/101123369X/34.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles

Books on the topic "Gilbarg problem"

1

Evans, Thomas L. Gilbert Law Summaries: Accounting & Finance for Lawyers. Gilberts Law Summaries, 2000.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Bratman, Michael E. Intention, Belief, Practical, Theoretical. Oxford University Press, 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190867850.003.0002.

Full text
Abstract:
This essay argues against an approach—one I call cognitivism—that tries to understand synchronic plan rationality as, at bottom a matter of theoretical rationality of belief. This approach is taken by, among others, Gilbert Harman, J. David Velleman, and R. Jay Wallace. I explain several problems for such cognitivism: there are problems posed by the possibility of false beliefs about what one intends; and there are problems posed by the need to distinguish intended means from expected side effects. In response to a challenge from Velleman, I sketch an alternative approach, one that sees these planning norms as fundamentally practical norms and that notes a parallel with Peter Strawson’s treatment of the framework of reactive attitudes.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles

Book chapters on the topic "Gilbarg problem"

1

Maaß, P. "Generalized Backus-Gilbert Methods." In Inverse Problems and Theoretical Imaging, 440–46. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg, 1990. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-75298-8_53.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Ang, Dang Dinh, Rudolf Gorenflo, Vy Khoi Le, and Dang Duc Trong. "3. Backus-Gilbert regularization of a moment problem." In Lecture Notes in Mathematics, 51–81. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg, 2002. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-540-45658-2_4.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Kaltenbacher, Barbara, Tram Thi Ngoc Nguyen, Anne Wald, and Thomas Schuster. "Parameter Identification for the Landau–Lifshitz–Gilbert Equation in Magnetic Particle Imaging." In Time-dependent Problems in Imaging and Parameter Identification, 377–412. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2021. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-57784-1_13.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Radman, Andrej. "Machinic Phylum and Architecture." In Proceedings of the 2020 DigitalFUTURES, 3–16. Singapore: Springer Singapore, 2021. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-981-33-4400-6_1.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractThe chapter draws on the anti-substantivist and anti-hylomorphic legacy of two significant Deleuze and Guattari’s interlocutors: Raymond Ruyer and Gilbert Simondon. Ruyer vehemently opposed the logic of mechanicism without regressing to (active) vitalism. His masterpiece Neofinalism, yet to be fully appreciated in architectural circles, is an ode to multiplicity or ‘absolute form’. The title is to be read as a challenge to the hegemony of the step-by-step causation and partes-extra-partes mereology. According to Ruyer, non-locality is the key, not only to the question of subjectivity, but to the problem of life itself. Simondon too shies away from the metaphysics of presence. For him, the process of individuation cannot be grasped on the basis of the fully formed individual. In other words, the knowledge of individuation is the individuation of knowledge. Simondon’s highest ambition in On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects was to integrate culture and technics (tekhne). The conviction that culture need not be antagonistic to technology is particularly pertinent to the ecologies of architecture. In the second half of the chapter, the affordance theory meets contemporary neurosciences.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

"Gilbert of Poitiers." In The Problem of Universals from Boethius to John of Salisbury, 235–70. BRILL, 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/9789004371156_011.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Lauter, Paul. "Teaching Nineteenth-Century Women Writers." In Canons and Contexts. Oxford University Press, 1991. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780195055931.003.0010.

Full text
Abstract:
During the last twenty years the opportunities and challenges to teach nineteenth-century American women writers have widened almost beyond the comprehension of those trained in previous decades. When I was in graduate school in the 1950s at Indiana and Yale, we read Emily Dickinson. Period. Today, that would be considered a scandal. The changes have been great, and good, but they have not been without problems. In this chapter I address a number of what I perceive as significant issues in teaching nineteenth-century American women writers. These I have named the problem of texts, the problem of history, the problem of context, the problem of subject, the problem of form, the problem of difference, and the problem of standards. As will be plain, the names are occasionally arbitrary and the categories somewhat overlap, but they may provide frameworks useful not only for those of us who were expected to know no more than Dickinson, but for those expecting to teach no less than Frances Ellen Watkins Harper and Lydia Maria Child. As recently as five years ago, a comprehensive course on nineteenth-century American women writers could only be taught by copious use of the copying machine. For if you wanted your students to know anything by Harper or Child—or even anything about them—you had no choice. That is, beyond the brief anthology selections of seventeen writers (including Harper) one finds in Gilbert and Gubar’s Literature by Women, the nine (spread over two volumes) in the Norton Anthology of American Literature, or the twelve in the recent Harper American Literature, few texts were available. The only piece of Child’s writing then in print was an excerpt from Hobomok (1824) in Lucy Freibert and Barbara White’s useful volume called Hidden Hands. Apart from that book, only Judith Fetterley’s pioneering 1985 collection, Provisions: A Reader from 19th-century American Women, had resurrected such women, and others like Caroline Kirkland, Fanny Fern and Alice Cary, from oblivion.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

McGoldrick, Beth. "Blending Front-End Analysis." In Human Performance Technology, 934–65. IGI Global, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.4018/978-1-5225-8356-1.ch046.

Full text
Abstract:
Performance problems come in all forms. The method presented in this chapter blends the models of three respected Performance improvement icons – Joe Harless, Thomas Gilbert, and Roger Chevalier. Their theoretical and practical approaches are applied to a case study. The three models – 13 Smart Questions (Front-end analysis), Behavior Engineering Model (BEM), and Updated BEM – when combined show ways practitioners can assess and improve performance. The practitioner will develop effective partnerships with clients, gain valuable perspectives on the issues, and their underlying causes. Finally the practitioner will be able to lead a department or an organization in fully analyzing problems and determining how best to solve them.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Narkunas, J. Paul. "Humanisms, Posthumanisms, and Their Discontents." In Reified Life, 1–36. Fordham University Press, 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.5422/fordham/9780823280308.003.0001.

Full text
Abstract:
The introduction outlines how we are living in an automated posthuman future with smart machines that blur boundary between human and non-human. The chapter also summarizes the general problems with humanism and posthumanism for instrumentalizing the human, and documents how both work too closely with neoliberalism and financial capital. How neoliberalism functions like culture and has created a world of economic ontology are also addressed. The author then traces problems with notions of agency based on subjectivity including the posthuman and object-oriented ontology, and proposes a different strategy for thinking agency along Gilbert Simondon’s notion of transindividuation that he calls ahuman. The ahuman is then defined as a stable figuration that embodies dynamic processes and forces that actually frame reality. The chapter ends with a discussion of the aesthetic as new figurations of existence that can be mobilized for alternative political purposes, as well as a brief outline of the chapters.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Rottschaefer, William A. "Moral Learning and Moral Realism." In The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, 37–43. Philosophy Documentation Center, 1998. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/wcp20-paideia199812269.

Full text
Abstract:
Although scientific naturalistic philosophers have been concerned with the role of scientific psychology in illuminating problems in moral psychology, they have paid less attention to the contributions that it might make to issues of moral ontology. In this paper, I illustrate how findings in moral developmental psychology illuminate and advance the discussion of a long-standing issue in moral ontology, that of moral realism. To do this, I examine Gilbert Harman and Nicholas Sturgeon's discussion of that issue. I contend that their explorations leave the issue unresolved. To break the stalemate, I appeal to empirical psychological findings about moral internalization-the process by which children acquire the capacity to act in terms of moral norms. I contend that these findings illuminate the issue, suggest a way to advance it, and tend to support a moral realist position.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Lavery, Grace E. "Not About Japan." In Quaint, Exquisite, 34–54. Princeton University Press, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.23943/princeton/9780691183626.003.0002.

Full text
Abstract:
This chapter aims to redirect an opera that is too often dislocated from that scene back within its boundaries. It explores the interpretive practices that have installed this certainty within critical approaches to such a semiotically complex work as Gilbert and Sullivan's The Mikado. Early productions proudly exhibited its Japanese qualities: the putatively authentic sword and costumes onstage; the Japanese women recruited to teach the British actors how to dance; the “Miya Sama” theme, incorporated almost without amendment from a Japanese source. It was not until the aftermath of the Russo-Japanese War of 1904–5, when the Japanese Empire confronted British audiences and critics with a newly threatening aspect, that critics collectively decided, never to recant, that the opera did not contain “a single joke against Japan,” as G. K. Chesterton put it, but was rather wholly designed to satirize and caricature British political culture. As such the affinities between The Mikado and a particular aspect of late-Victorian Orientalism have been obscured, and the semiotic problem Japanese culture posed to Victorians has been oversimplified.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles

Conference papers on the topic "Gilbarg problem"

1

Chou, Min-Li, Fan-Hsiu Huang, and Hsien-Chin Chiu. "A low LO power V-band Gilbert-cell down-conversion mixer using 90 nm CMOS technology." In 2013 International Conference on Computational Problem-solving (ICCP). IEEE, 2013. http://dx.doi.org/10.1109/iccps.2013.6893515.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Barrows, Lawrence J., and Mark E. Edwards. "Backus‐Gilbert Inversion of Electrical Resistivity Soundings and Its Application to Solid‐Waste Landfills." In Symposium on the Application of Geophysics to Engineering and Environmental Problems 1995. Environment and Engineering Geophysical Society, 1995. http://dx.doi.org/10.4133/1.2922190.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

J. Barrows, Lawrence, and Mark E. Edwards. "Backus-Gilbert Inversion Of Electrical Resistivity Soundings And Its Application To Solid-Waste Landfills." In 8th EEGS Symposium on the Application of Geophysics to Engineering and Environmental Problems. European Association of Geoscientists & Engineers, 1995. http://dx.doi.org/10.3997/2214-4609-pdb.206.1995_067.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Papadonikolakis, Markos, and Christos-Savvas Bouganis. "Efficient FPGA mapping of Gilbert’s algorithm for SVM training on large-scale classification problems." In 2008 International Conference on Field Programmable Logic and Applications (FPL). IEEE, 2008. http://dx.doi.org/10.1109/fpl.2008.4629968.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
We offer discounts on all premium plans for authors whose works are included in thematic literature selections. Contact us to get a unique promo code!

To the bibliography