Academic literature on the topic 'Crime – Philosophy'
Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles
Consult the lists of relevant articles, books, theses, conference reports, and other scholarly sources on the topic 'Crime – Philosophy.'
Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.
You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.
Journal articles on the topic "Crime – Philosophy"
Djuniarti, Evi. "The Criminal Liability of Corporations as Crime Perpetrators." Jurnal Penelitian Hukum De Jure 21, no. 3 (September 28, 2021): 311. http://dx.doi.org/10.30641/dejure.2021.v21.311-320.
Full textKerimov, A. D., and E. V. Halipova. "The evil and crime: moral and legal dimension." Russian Journal of Legal Studies 2, no. 2 (June 15, 2015): 234–41. http://dx.doi.org/10.17816/rjls18059.
Full textAn, Ran, and Peng Liu. "Research on the Environmental Philosophy of China’s Environmental Crime Legislation from the Perspective of Ecological Civilization Construction." International Journal of Environmental Research and Public Health 20, no. 2 (January 13, 2023): 1517. http://dx.doi.org/10.3390/ijerph20021517.
Full textAlzouabi, Lina. "A Reading of Charles Dickens' Hard Times (1854) As a Crime Novel." International Journal of Linguistics, Literature and Translation 4, no. 4 (April 29, 2021): 193–99. http://dx.doi.org/10.32996/ijllt.2021.4.4.21.
Full textGolik, Yuri Vladimirovich. "Philosophy, Morality, Fight against Crime." Journal of Russian Law 25, no. 12 (July 14, 2022): 1. http://dx.doi.org/10.12737/jrl.2021.143.
Full textMASLENNIKOVA, Larisa, Tatyana VILKOVA, Andrew SOBENIN, Kseniia TABOLINA, and Tatyana TOPILINA. "Using Online Services to Report a Crime." WISDOM 18, no. 2 (June 25, 2021): 120–28. http://dx.doi.org/10.24234/wisdom.v18i2.450.
Full textShepitko, Valery Yu, and Mykhaylo V. Shepitko. "The role of forensic science and forensic examination in international cooperation in the investigation of crimes." Journal of the National Academy of Legal Sciences of Ukraine 28, no. 1 (March 24, 2021): 179–86. http://dx.doi.org/10.37635/jnalsu.28(1).2021.179-186.
Full textMcGregor, Rafe. "A Literary Aesthetics of War Crime." Croatian journal of philosophy 21, no. 61 (May 21, 2021): 135–53. http://dx.doi.org/10.52685/cjp.21.1.8.
Full textChehtman, Alejandro. "Contemporary Approaches to the Philosophy of Crimes against Humanity." International Criminal Law Review 14, no. 4-5 (July 31, 2014): 813–35. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/15718123-01405005.
Full textSkoromnyi, Danylo A. "Legal entities' crime prevention: Foreign experience and prospects of application in Ukraine." Journal of the National Academy of Legal Sciences of Ukraine 28, no. 3 (September 17, 2021): 301–10. http://dx.doi.org/10.37635/jnalsu.28(3).2021.301-310.
Full textDissertations / Theses on the topic "Crime – Philosophy"
Fatic, Aleksandar. "Punishment and restorative crime-handling : a social theory of trust." Phd thesis, Canberra, ACT : The Australian National University, 1995. http://hdl.handle.net/1885/143619.
Full textGonçalves, Piterson Balmat. "A crise do dever em crime e castigo, de Dostoiévski." Universidade de São Paulo, 2016. http://www.teses.usp.br/teses/disponiveis/2/2139/tde-26072016-104943/.
Full textIn this dissertation we seeks to show the crisis of moral duty in Crime and Punishment, Dostoevsky, example of our own contemporary crisis, while we seek to investigate the outlines of a principle of justice brought by Kantian duty. Thereafter, we intend to show how this principle of justice can be shared by Dostoevsky, as the novelist, in his ideal of moral community, continues the ethical sense proposed in the Kantian duty, through which overcomes the crisis that spear the novel.
Hall, Matthew Peter. "Putting victims of crime 'at the heart' of criminal justice : practice, politics and philosophy." Thesis, University of Sheffield, 2007. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.443512.
Full textJohnson, Andrew. "Crime, governance and numbers : a genealogy of counting crime in New South Wales." Thesis, View thesis, 2000. http://handle.uws.edu.au:8081/1959.7/535.
Full textGiddens, Thomas Philip. "Comics, crime, and the moral self : an interdisciplinary study of criminal identity." Thesis, University of Exeter, 2011. http://hdl.handle.net/10036/3622.
Full textBlaas, Fey-Constanze. "Double criminality in international extradition law." Thesis, Stellenbosch : Stellenbosch University, 2003. http://hdl.handle.net/10019.1/53398.
Full textENGLISH ABSTRACT: The object of the thesis is to examine the content and status of the double criminality principle in international extradition law. The double criminality principle says a fugitive c annat be extradited unless the conduct for which his extradition is sought is criminal in both the requesting state and the requested state. This thesis is based on a study of sources of international law and domestic law and ideas presented in legal literature. The double criminality principle has developed over several centuries and it has been embraced by most states in one form or the other. The principle serves several purposes, of which the most dominant is the notion of state sovereignty. States apply the double criminality principle differently due to its multiple rationale. Legal literature has distinguished two main methods of interpretation, called interpretation in abstracto and in concreto. Whereas the in abstracto method focuses on the theoretical punishability of the conduct, the in concreto method attaches importance to all factual, personal and legal aspects. There are also ways of interpretation that are a combination of these two methods. Most states can be classified into one of the two main groups of interpretation, but in general most states have adopted a specific method of interpretation that is unique to each particular state. There is thus no uniform method of interpretation in international extradition law. This thesis attempts to determine whether the double criminality principle has become a rule of customary international law. Though most instruments on international or domestic extradition law include the double criminality principle, the strong disagreement among legal scholars as to the legal status of the principle leads to the conclusion that the double criminality principle is not a rule of international law today. This thesis contains an examination of whether the principle of double criminality can be classified as an international human rights norm. Though the principle of double criminality has striking similarities with human rights as it partly aims at protecting individuals facing extradition, there are also a number of aspects that distinguish the principle from traditional human rights. This is partly attributable to the fact that international extradition law is not the arena where general international human rights have developed. It is therefore concluded that the double criminality principle does not form part of international human rights law.
AFRIKAANSE OPSOMMING: Die oogmerk van hierdie tesis is om die inhoud en status van die beginsel van dubbelkriminaliteit in internasionale uitleweringsreg te ondersoek. Hierdie beginsel behels dat die handeling ten opsigte waarvan die uitlewering versoek is, misdade in beide die staat wat uitlewering versoek as die staat waarvan uitlewering versoek word, is. Die metode wat hierdie tesis onderlê is 'n literatuurstudie van bronne in die internasionale en nasionale reg. Die dubbelkriminaliteitsbeginsel het oor etlike eeue ontwikkel. Dit word gevind in die meeste regstelsels. Die beginsel dien verskeie oogmerke, waarvan staatsoewereiniteit sekerlik die belangrikste is. State pas die beginselop verskillende maniere toe weens die verskeie bestaansredes vir die beginsel. Regsliteratuur tref 'n onderskeid tussen twee belangrike metodes van interpretasie, naamlik die in abstracto en in concreto benaderings. Terwyl die in abstracto metode op die teoretiese strafbaarheid van die handeling fokus, plaas die in concreto benadering klem op die feitelike, persoonlike en konkrete regsaspekte. Daar is kombinasies van hierdie metodes. Meeste state kan geklassifiseer word volgens die twee benaderings, maar tog pas state hierdie benaderings by hul besondere behoeftes aan. Daar is dus geen uniforme metode van interpretasie in internasionale uitleweringsreg nie. Hierdie tesis poog om te bepaal of die dubbelkriminaliteitsbeginsel 'n reël van gemeenregtelike internasionale reg geword het. Alhoewel meeste wetgewing op die terrein van internasionale en nasionale uitleweringsreg die beginsel van dubbelkriminalitiet insluit, is daar sterk meningsverskilonder regsgeleerdes tov die status van die beinsel. Die gevolgtrekking is dat die beginsel nie 'n algemene reël van die internasionale reg is nie. Ten slotte word daar gekyk of die dubbelkriminaliteitsbeginsel as 'n beginsel van internasionale menseregte geklassifiseer kan word. Alhoewel die beginsel ooreemste met menseregtenorme toon - veral die beskerming van die individu in uitleweringsaangeleenthede - is daar 'n aantal aspekte wat d it van menseregte 0 nderskei. I nternasionale uitleweringsreg en internasionale menseregte deel nie dieselfde ontwikkelingsgeskiedenis nie. Die gevolgtrekking is dus dat die dubbelkriminaliteitsbeginsel nie deel vorm van internasionale menseregte nie.
Parsley, Stephen. "Rethinking Legal Retribution." Digital Archive @ GSU, 2011. http://digitalarchive.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/98.
Full textArsego, Djonatan. "Teoria Hegeliana da pena e administração da justiça." reponame:Repositório Institucional da UCS, 2016. https://repositorio.ucs.br/handle/11338/1846.
Full textSubmitted by Ana Guimarães Pereira (agpereir@ucs.br) on 2017-03-17T14:06:23Z No. of bitstreams: 1 Dissertacao Djonatan Arsego.pdf: 1436127 bytes, checksum: 08783847f1029eec9349721f4514dfd8 (MD5)
Made available in DSpace on 2017-03-17T14:06:23Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 Dissertacao Djonatan Arsego.pdf: 1436127 bytes, checksum: 08783847f1029eec9349721f4514dfd8 (MD5) Previous issue date: 2017-03-17
The study developed in this dissertation deals with the Hegelian concept of the administration of justice from the work entitled “Filosofia do Direito” (legal philosophy). (FD, 2003). This Hegelian conception of the administration of the law is part of the concept of the civil society encompassed in ethics, the third part of the philosophy of law. This subsection is composed of paragraphs 209-229, and deals with the application of the law. This paper examines if the institution of the law is real and effective for the society and for its citizens; how the laws are formed and applied in social groups, and why they are so important to the stability and coexistence of people in a state according to the Hegelian theory of law. But how can it be said that the Hegelian right, in its theory of punishment, is stable, in view of the variations in the application of laws? Also, in view of the different ways offenders are judged? These answers will be given in court by the penalty chosen, which is given to each particular case, analyzing the intention for which the citizen has deviated from interacting with other members of society and seeing the damage caused by the offenders. This work also deals with the problems of the "right to say no" and the "right of necessity or emergency". It also incorporates the concepts of intent and unintentional guilt present in Hegelian morality. For the penalty to be effective, it is required that society sees it in the form of codes, which will allow all citizens to recognize them as models, and at the same time as costumes needed for a good living. Therefore, it is important to understand how the laws are formed and actualized in society, as this is the reason for their existence.
Rewinski, Zachary D. "Dostoevsky and Tolstoy's Oblique Responses to the Epidemic of Chernyshevskian Philosophy." Oberlin College Honors Theses / OhioLINK, 2010. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc_num=oberlin1277852390.
Full textWirts, Amelia Marie. "Criminal Oppression: A Non-Ideal Theory of Criminal Law and Punishment." Thesis, Boston College, 2020. http://hdl.handle.net/2345/bc-ir:108954.
Full textThis dissertation defines and defends the concept of ‘criminal oppression.’ Criminal oppression occurs when people are excluded from full participation in important social and political institutions because they are perceived to have violated certain community norms. Oppression is primarily a structural phenomenon, in which practices of formal and informal institutions unjustly harm people based on group membership. In structural oppression, there is rarely an individual who can be said to be responsible for the oppression, but I argue that at times, individuals may also be agents of oppression when they create, perpetuate, or exacerbate structural oppression. Applying this theory of oppression, the criminal justice system in the United States is an oppressive structure that unjustly harms those considered to be ‘criminals’ through a variety of practices. There are three categories of unjust practices: policing, adjudication and punishment, and collateral effects of arrest and conviction. These three categories of practices create the social group ‘criminals’ by subjecting certain people to these kinds of treatments. I use the word ‘criminal’ to describe those who are treated as criminals by police, the courts, and even private individuals like employers. To be a ‘criminal,’ it is not necessary that one has committed a crime or been convicted of a crime. Racial and criminal oppression deeply related historically and conceptually. Nevertheless, they are distinct kinds of oppression. In the United States, those who are not racially oppressed but are ‘criminals’ face many of the same unjust obstacles as those who are racially oppressed in addition to being ‘criminals.’ Some may argue that ‘criminals’ duly convicted of crimes deserve to be socially and politically excluded. But, I argue that the criminal justice system is not properly conceived of as an apolitical institution that can assess moral blameworthiness. Nor should it be able to offer punishments that amount to social and political exclusion. Instead, the criminal justice system is one political institution amongst many, and it ought to be governed by the same principles of liberty and equality that govern other political institutions. Criminal law’s proper function is to facilitate government as a system social cooperation. Therefore, it ought to respond to criminal acts with actions designed to promote inclusion rather than exclusion. Moreover, even if someone has committed a crime, that does not mean that they ought to be subject to violence or permanent second-class status. Finally, I address specific, feminism-driven arguments for using the criminal justice system to fight violence against women. Some feminists argue that the expressivist function of punishment—the ability of punishment to express disapproval and disavowal—makes it a perfect tool for fighting the normalization of violence against women. The problem, they contend, is that this violence is under-punished in the United States, and the solution to ending violence against women is to increase prosecutions and advocate for harsher punishments because punishment will change the social norms and make violence against women rarer. To this, I argue that those who create laws or mete out punishments do not have control over the social meaning of punishment with precision. The historical and present-day oppressive features of criminal law and punishment interfere with the ability of prosecution and punishment to condemn certain types of acts without also condemning people. Thus, feminists who try to use the criminal justice system to fight gender-based violence will find it to be ineffective and potentially harmful to the already oppressed group of ‘criminals.” Chapter 1argues that ‘criminals’ are oppressed using a structural model of oppression that focuses on how collections of institutional policies and practices can create and maintain unjust power relations between groups of people. I will also use an externalist theory of group identity to argue that being arrested or convicted of a crime is not necessary or sufficient for membership in the social group ‘criminal.’ Chapter 2 explains the relationship between racial oppression and the oppression of ‘criminals,’ noting the historical development of the modern prison system. Chapter 3 argues that the proper role of criminal law is to support systems of social cooperation, not to punish pre-political wrongs. I will suggest that criminal law is in essence part of the social contract, not a separate sphere of justice to which distinctive, retributive principles apply. Instead, the criminal law cannot determine moral blameworthiness and is only justified in sanctioning rule violations for the sake of supporting social cooperation in a society whose institutions are worth supporting. In Chapter 4, I propose a feminist, expressivist defense of the use of prosecution and harsh punishment as a response to rape and domestic violence that takes the structural nature of violence against women into account. Chapter 5, however, demonstrates why even this theory cannot justify incarceration in the non-ideal sphere because of the oppressive history and practice of the American criminal justice system
Thesis (PhD) — Boston College, 2020
Submitted to: Boston College. Graduate School of Arts and Sciences
Discipline: Philosophy
Books on the topic "Crime – Philosophy"
A, Arrigo Bruce, and Williams Christopher R. 1972-, eds. Philosophy, crime, and criminology. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 2006.
Find full textBaudrillard, Jean. The perfect crime. London: Verso, 1996.
Find full textBaudrillard, Jean. Le crime parfait. Paris: Galilée, 1995.
Find full textTamburrini, Claudio Marcello. Crime and punishment? Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell International, 1992.
Find full textPenal philosophy. New Brunswick, N.J: Transaction Publishers, 2001.
Find full textCrime prevention. Cullompton, Devon: Willan, 2009.
Find full textFrankel, Paul Ellen, Miller Fred Dycus 1944-, and Paul Jeffrey, eds. Crime, culpability, and remedy. Cambridge, MA, USA: Blackwell, 1990.
Find full textValier, Claire. Theories of crime and punishment. New York: Longman, 2001.
Find full textTheories of crime and punishment. Harlow: Longman, 2002.
Find full textCrime, governance and existential predicaments. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2011.
Find full textBook chapters on the topic "Crime – Philosophy"
Canêdo, Carlos Augusto. "Crime." In Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy, 1–4. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 2022. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6730-0_486-1.
Full textAtenasio, David. "Philosophy of Crime." In Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy, 1–9. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 2022. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6730-0_1099-1.
Full textLynch, Michael J. "Conflict and Crime." In The Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Criminology, 84–101. Hoboken, NJ, USA: John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781119011385.ch5.
Full textMaltz, Michael D., Andrew C. Gordon, and Warren Friedman. "Philosophy Underlying the Technical Approach." In Mapping Crime in Its Community Setting, 44–59. New York, NY: Springer New York, 1991. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4612-3042-7_5.
Full textCigüela Sola, Javier. "Crime and of the Poor from Recognition Perspective." In Philosophy and Poverty, 299–321. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-45795-2_14.
Full textYusef, Kideste Wilder, and Tseleq Yusef. "Criminalizing Race, Racializing Crime." In The Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Criminology, 272–88. Hoboken, NJ, USA: John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781119011385.ch16.
Full textRebellon, Cesar J., and Paul Anskat. "Crime, Deviance, and Social Control." In The Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Criminology, 189–205. Hoboken, NJ, USA: John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781119011385.ch11.
Full textŠkvorecký, Josef. "The Case of Lewis S. Feuer, Crime Writer." In Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 419–23. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 1988. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2873-2_23.
Full textBecker, Peter. "Researching Crime and Criminals in the 19th Century." In The Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Criminology, 32–47. Hoboken, NJ, USA: John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781119011385.ch2.
Full textEassey, John M., and Marvin D. Krohn. "Differential Association, Differential Social Organization, and White-Collar Crime." In The Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Criminology, 156–72. Hoboken, NJ, USA: John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781119011385.ch9.
Full textConference papers on the topic "Crime – Philosophy"
Miao, Miao. "The Philosophy of Crime and Punishment and Existentialism in WoodymAllen s Film." In International Conference on Education, Language, Art and Intercultural Communication (ICELAIC-14). Paris, France: Atlantis Press, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.2991/icelaic-14.2014.190.
Full textGolubovsky, Vladimir Yuryevich, Igor Yurievich Nikodimov, and Elena Anatolyevna Mironova. "Judicial Support of High-Tech Crime Research." In International Scientific Conference on Philosophy of Education, Law and Science in the Era of Globalization (PELSEG 2020). Paris, France: Atlantis Press, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.2991/assehr.k.200723.052.
Full textLi, Xinxun. "Analysis of Racial Discrimination in Artificial Intelligence from the Perspective of Social Media, Search Engines, and Future Crime Prediction Systems." In 6th International Conference on Contemporary Education, Social Sciences and Humanities. (Philosophy of Being Human as the Core of Interdisciplinary Research) (ICCESSH 2021). Paris, France: Atlantis Press, 2021. http://dx.doi.org/10.2991/assehr.k.210902.029.
Full textZaharia, Virginia. "The Philosophical Vision of Legal Punishment." In World Lumen Congress 2021, May 26-30, 2021, Iasi, Romania. LUMEN Publishing House, 2022. http://dx.doi.org/10.18662/wlc2021/73.
Full textKhramchenkova, Rezida. "ORIGINS OF GLAZED CERAMICS KAZAN KREMLIN: CRIMEA - BULGARIA � KAZAN." In SGEM 2014 Scientific SubConference on ANTHROPOLOGY, ARCHAEOLOGY, HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY. Stef92 Technology, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.5593/sgemsocial2014/b31/s9.050.
Full textGolubovsky, Vladimir Yuryevich, Igor Yurievich Nikodimov, and Elena Anatolyevna Mironova. "Legal, Tactical and Forensic Support of the Judicial Investigation of Crimes." In International Scientific Conference on Philosophy of Education, Law and Science in the Era of Globalization (PELSEG 2020). Paris, France: Atlantis Press, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.2991/assehr.k.200723.029.
Full textKaliuzhnyi, A. N., and N. G. Shurukhnov. "The Use of Automated Systems in the Investigation of Crimes Aimed at Personal Freedom." In International Scientific Conference on Philosophy of Education, Law and Science in the Era of Globalization (PELSEG 2020). Paris, France: Atlantis Press, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.2991/assehr.k.200723.038.
Full textTabatchikova, Anastasiya. "Problems of Balancing Private and Public Interests of States in the Criminalisation of International Crimes." In The Public/Private in Modern Civilization, the 22nd Russian Scientific-Practical Conference (with international participation) (Yekaterinburg, April 16-17, 2020). Liberal Arts University – University for Humanities, Yekaterinburg, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.35853/ufh-public/private-2020-22.
Full text