Dissertationen zum Thema „Philosophy of art“
Geben Sie eine Quelle nach APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard und anderen Zitierweisen an
Machen Sie sich mit Top-50 Dissertationen für die Forschung zum Thema "Philosophy of art" bekannt.
Neben jedem Werk im Literaturverzeichnis ist die Option "Zur Bibliographie hinzufügen" verfügbar. Nutzen Sie sie, wird Ihre bibliographische Angabe des gewählten Werkes nach der nötigen Zitierweise (APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver usw.) automatisch gestaltet.
Sie können auch den vollen Text der wissenschaftlichen Publikation im PDF-Format herunterladen und eine Online-Annotation der Arbeit lesen, wenn die relevanten Parameter in den Metadaten verfügbar sind.
Sehen Sie die Dissertationen für verschiedene Spezialgebieten durch und erstellen Sie Ihre Bibliographie auf korrekte Weise.
Lafferty, Michael Gerald. „Arthur Danto's philosophy of art“. Thesis, University of Warwick, 2006. http://wrap.warwick.ac.uk/42211/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleGustafsson, Daniel. „A philosophy of Christian art“. Thesis, University of York, 2014. http://etheses.whiterose.ac.uk/8052/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuellePeters, Julia Helene. „Art and philosophy in Hegel's system“. Thesis, University College London (University of London), 2009. http://discovery.ucl.ac.uk/18022/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleThompson, Seth Aaron. „Art Unfettered: Bergson and a Fluid Conception of Art“. Thesis, University of North Texas, 2018. https://digital.library.unt.edu/ark:/67531/metadc1248388/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleMcGuiggan, James Camien. „This is art : a defence of R.G. Collingwood's philosophy of art“. Thesis, University of Southampton, 2017. https://eprints.soton.ac.uk/407958/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleAl-Obaid, Hanan. „Philosophy of Islamic ornament in Islamic art“. Thesis, Cardiff University, 2005. http://orca.cf.ac.uk/55634/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleEngstrom, Timothy Hildreth. „Pragmatic rhetoric and the art of philosophy“. Thesis, University of Edinburgh, 1988. http://hdl.handle.net/1842/18866.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleRampley, Matthew. „Dialectics of contingency : Nietzsche's philosophy of art“. Thesis, University of St Andrews, 1993. http://hdl.handle.net/10023/14775.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleFidalgo, Christopher J. „Art, Gaut and Games: the Case for Why Some Video Games Are Art“. Digital Archive @ GSU, 2012. http://digitalarchive.gsu.edu/philosophy_hontheses/5.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleHanson, Louise Mary. „Conceptual art : what is it?“ Thesis, University of Oxford, 2011. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:1ce65d49-6864-4a29-8600-5c54e405ef5e.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleMillsop, Rebecca Victoria. „Precisifying art pluralism“. Thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, 2016. http://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/107093.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleCataloged from PDF version of thesis.
Includes bibliographical references (pages 105-110).
This dissertation explores the legitimacy of art pluralism-the thesis that there are multiple, valid accounts of art. In 2011 Mag Uidhir and Magnus introduced the idea of art pluralism to revive the debate over the definition of art. This discussion has been pushed aside over the past half a century because all proposed accounts prove fallible under scrutiny. The overarching goal of this dissertation is to determine how this new approach-art pluralism-might prove useful in obtaining a satisfactory theory of art. In the first chapter, I introduce art pluralism with the aid of species pluralism the thesis that there are multiple, legitimate species accounts. I go on to criticize the arguments for art pluralism provided by Mag Uidhir and Magnus and go on to provide a stronger, direct argument for art pluralism. In the second chapter, I consider the nature of pluralism in depth by introducing the notion of a complex kind. I claim that all pluralistic kinds are complex kinds and that there are multiple ways a kind can be complex. A kind is complex if and only if more than one account is required to explain its unification and working out the nature of this unification results in the precisification of that complex kind. I go on to precisify species pluralism as an example of this process. In the third and fourth chapters, I demonstrate how each of the relevant art accounts-institutional, historical, and aesthetic-succeed and fail in providing the satisfactory account of art on their own. Instead we must understand these accounts as structurally dependent on one another. I describe the result of this particular structural dependence focal-looping pluralism. In the conclusion, I acknowledge the importance of pluralism throughout the narrative of this dissertation but I am forced to question whether or not the thesis I end up arguing for is really best understood as pluralistic. I argue that art is best understood as a complex, not a pluralistic, kind and that the monist/pluralist dichotomy should be understood as less informative than the simple/complex kind distinction more generally.
by Rebecca Victoria Millsop.
Ph. D.
Weis, Kristin K. „Art as Negation: A Defense of Conceptual Art as Art“. Kent State University / OhioLINK, 2016. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc_num=kent1461602608.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleFarrelly-Jackson, Steven. „Universalism, morality, and art“. Thesis, University of Oxford, 1992. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.333323.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleThomas, Christopher. „The place of art in Spinoza's naturalist philosophy“. Thesis, University of Aberdeen, 2017. http://digitool.abdn.ac.uk:80/webclient/DeliveryManager?pid=237177.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleBuydens, Mireille. „Formalisme et aformalisme: essai sur le statut de la forme et du regard au travers d'une analyse du maniérisme“. Doctoral thesis, Universite Libre de Bruxelles, 1994. http://hdl.handle.net/2013/ULB-DIPOT:oai:dipot.ulb.ac.be:2013/212664.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleNickels, Zachary. „The Art of Loneliness“. Kent State University Honors College / OhioLINK, 2005. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc_num=ksuhonors1462549085.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleRinaldi, Juan. „Art and geopolitics : politics and autonomy in Argentine contemporary art“. Thesis, Kingston University, 2013. http://eprints.kingston.ac.uk/26287/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleNorth, John Harry. „Wincklemann's philosophy of art : a prelude to German classicism“. Thesis, Queen Mary, University of London, 2011. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.538667.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleHernandez, Brian. „Nihilism and the Formulation of a Philosophy of Art“. Thesis, University of North Texas, 2011. https://digital.library.unt.edu/ark:/67531/metadc67991/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleClancy, Catherine. „Poiesis and obstruction in art practice“. Thesis, University of the Arts London, 2015. http://ualresearchonline.arts.ac.uk/7842/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleBresnahan, Aili. „Dance As Art: A Studio-Based Account“. Diss., Temple University Libraries, 2012. http://cdm16002.contentdm.oclc.org/cdm/ref/collection/p245801coll10/id/173544.
Der volle Inhalt der QuellePh.D.
This dissertation is an attempt to articulate the conviction, born of ten years of intensive experience in learning and practicing to be a dance performer, that the dance performer, through collaboration with the choreographer, makes an important contribution to how we can and do understand artistic dance performance. Further, this contribution involves on-the-fly-thinking-while-doing in which the movement of the dancer's body is run through by consciousness. Some of this activity of "consciousness" in movement may not be part of the deliberative mentality of which the agent is aware; it may instead be something that is part of our body's natural and acquired plan for how to move in the world that is shaped by years of artistic and cultural training and practice. The result is a qualitative and visceral performance that can, although need not, be a representation of some deliberative thought or intention that a dancer can articulate beforehand. It is also the sort of thinking movement that in many cases can be conceived as expression; an utterance of dance artists that is not limited to the communication of emotion that can be appreciated and understood, at least in principle, by a public or audience. What this means for the Philosophy of Dance as Art includes the following: 1) there may not always be a stable, fixed "work" of dance art that can be identified, going forward, as the only relevant work on which critical and philosophical attention should be focused because of variable, contingent and irreducibly individual features of live dance performances, attributable in large part to the efforts, style and improvisation of particular dance performers; 2) the experience of dance artists is relevant to understand dance as art because experiential evidence of practice can supplement and ground the appreciable properties that we can detect in artistic dance performances; 3) artistic dance performance can be conceived as expression without being expressive of either an artist's felt emotion or of human emotion in general - no particular content is needed as long as there is a content; 4) artistic dance performance conceived as expression can, but need not, function as representation in both the strong (imitative) and weak (referential) sense; and 5) artistic dance performance is real, not illusory and not necessarily either a transformation or transfiguration of the real. Dance as art, like theatre, like music and even, perhaps, like painting, sculpture and architecture, although in less clearly artist-present, extemporaneous and embodied ways, is human-constructed, human-understood, human-driven and a full, rich, interactive and meaningful part of human life.
Temple University--Theses
Walsh, Dale. „Art and secular spirituality“. Thesis, McGill University, 2001. http://digitool.Library.McGill.CA:80/R/?func=dbin-jump-full&object_id=33946.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleWeh, Michael. „Being art - a study in ontology“. Thesis, St Andrews, 2007. http://hdl.handle.net/10023/213.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleAndersson, Asa K. „Intimations of intimacy : phenomenological encounters between contemporary art and philosophy“. Thesis, Staffordshire University, 1999. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.299938.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleBartlett, Mark. „Chronotopology and the scientific-aesthetic in philosophy, literature and art /“. Diss., Digital Dissertations Database. Restricted to UC campuses, 2005. http://uclibs.org/PID/11984.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleLynch, Liam Joseph. „Complex truth from simple beauty: Oscar Wilde’s philosophy of art“. Thesis, Curtin University, 2014. http://hdl.handle.net/20.500.11937/195.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleWillis, Gary C. „Contemporary art: the key issues: art, philosophy and politics in the context of contemporary cultural production“. Connect to thesis, 2007. http://repository.unimelb.edu.au/10187/2245.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleLopez, Noelle Regina. „The art of Platonic love“. Thesis, University of Oxford, 2014. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:5e9b2d70-49d9-4e75-b445-fcb0bfecdcef.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleGriffin, Daniel. „The Role of Poetry and Language in Hegel's Philosophy of Art“. Digital Archive @ GSU, 2011. http://digitalarchive.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/90.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleAldous, Veronica. „An exploration of the transcending experience in the art-making process“. Thesis, Edith Cowan University, Research Online, Perth, Western Australia, 2002. https://ro.ecu.edu.au/theses/744.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleKopsiafti, Ioanna. „Cassirer's philosophy of symbolic forms and the problem of pictorial art“. Thesis, University of Oxford, 1999. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.297363.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleThomson, Katherine J. M. „The art museum at the end of art, Arthur C. Danto's Philosophy of art and its implications for the posthistorical museum“. Thesis, National Library of Canada = Bibliothèque nationale du Canada, 1998. http://www.collectionscanada.ca/obj/s4/f2/dsk2/tape15/PQDD_0010/MQ31259.pdf.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleKieran, Matthew Laurence. „The nature and value of art“. Thesis, University of St Andrews, 1995. http://hdl.handle.net/10023/14807.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleHouse, Theresa L. „Making authentic connections between art and life an evolution of student engagement in the process of learning art in an elementary classroom /“. Ohio : Ohio University, 2009. http://www.ohiolink.edu/etd/view.cgi?ohiou1213021116.
Der volle Inhalt der QuellePalucci, Piera. „Emergence of an art education philosophy through a personal narrative inquiry“. Thesis, National Library of Canada = Bibliothèque nationale du Canada, 2000. http://www.collectionscanada.ca/obj/s4/f2/dsk1/tape3/PQDD_0020/MQ47867.pdf.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleKim, Byoungjae. „Sympathy and reflection in Hume's philosophy : mind, morals, art and politics“. Thesis, Durham University, 2018. http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/12958/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleMiyoshi, Akihiko. „Art and authenticity /“. Link to online version, 2005. https://ritdml.rit.edu/dspace/handle/1850/1106.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleAllen, Rika. „The anthropology of art and the art of anthropology : a complex relationship“. Thesis, Stellenbosch : University of Stellenbosch, 2008. http://hdl.handle.net/10019.1/2304.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleIt has been said that anthropology operates in “liminal spaces” which can be defined as “spaces between disciplines”. This study will explore the space where the fields of art and anthropology meet in order to discover the epistemological and representational challenges that arise from this encounter. The common ground on which art and anthropology engage can be defined in terms of their observational and knowledge producing practices. Both art and anthropology rely on observational skills and varying forms of visual literacy to collect and represent data. Anthropologists represent their data mostly in written form by means of ethnographic accounts, and artists represent their findings by means of imaginative artistic mediums such as painting, sculpture, filmmaking and music. Following the so-called ‘ethnographic turn’, contemporary artists have adopted an ‘anthropological’ gaze, including methodologies, such as fieldwork, in their appropriation of other cultures. Anthropologists, on the other hand, in the wake of the ‘writing culture’ critique of the 1980s, are starting to explore new forms of visual research and representational practices that go beyond written texts.
Rausch, Juliana Adele. „The New Journalism as Avant-Garde Art“. Diss., Temple University Libraries, 2017. http://cdm16002.contentdm.oclc.org/cdm/ref/collection/p245801coll10/id/443068.
Der volle Inhalt der QuellePh.D.
Can journalism be avant-garde? This question arises from the body of work produced by the New Journalists, whose leading figures include Truman Capote, Tom Wolfe, Joan Didion, and Norman Mailer. Today, this question is urgent for considerations of the journalist’s role within a political landscape increasingly hostile to the news media. Yet it is a question that has not been sufficiently explored in the field of literary study. Scholars of literary journalism have identified the features of an experimental journalism, traced its historical origins, and made claims about how to situate the New Journalism generically. While important, this scholarship overlooks the relationship between experimentation with conventional journalistic form and similar experimentations in other artistic fields. As a result, the stakes of the New Journalism’s experimentations with conventional reporting have not been sufficiently mined. In order to remedy this, I place the New Journalism within a broader history of avant-garde art. The agitation of mainstream journalistic practice undertaken by each of the writers above was spurred by a questioning of a foundational journalistic practice: objectivity. The New Journalists challenged the authority of fact and its capacity to represent the human condition. This challenge to objectivity drove an experimentation with journalistic form that produced a deeply innovative body of work; however, these innovations are not merely formal. They also call into question the epistemological assumptions that tether journalism to a phenomenal world assumed to be fully representable. Significantly, the challenges to objectivity posed by the New Journalists parallel the challenges to representation posed by avant-garde artists like Paul Cezanne and Karel Appel. My dissertation thus situates the challenges to journalistic form undertaken by the New Journalists within a broader history of artistic experimentation and demonstrates that the significance of these experimentations exceeds the fields in which they occur. These arguments provide a framework for understanding not only the formal innovations of avant-garde artists, but also the epistemological consequences, and ethical imperatives, inherent in these innovations. My understanding of avant-garde art is informed by the work of Jean-Francois Lyotard. Over the course of his career, Lyotard illuminated the philosophical dimensions of artistic innovation. For Lyotard, one of the hallmarks of avant-garde experimentation is its ability to confront and redress problems across a variety of discursive fields. That is, Lyotard values avant-garde experimentation because it responds to discourses beyond its own, and much of Lyotard’s writing about avant-garde art establishes connections between artistic innovation and broader issues of ethics, politics, and justice. Over the course of this dissertation, I demonstrate how the New Journalism participates in this tradition by asking questions about the role and responsibility of the reporter through the self-conscious development of an experimental journalistic aesthetic.
Temple University--Theses
Martel, Marie D. „L'oeuvre comme interaction : anti-textualisme, actionnalisme et ontologie écologique“. Thesis, McGill University, 2004. http://digitool.Library.McGill.CA:80/R/?func=dbin-jump-full&object_id=85187.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleMachado, Oscar A. „A Philosophy of Architecture“. Scholarly Repository, 2009. http://scholarlyrepository.miami.edu/oa_theses/205.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleMatuk, Nyla Jean. „Charles Taylor on art and moral sources : a pragmatist re-evaluation“. Thesis, McGill University, 1994. http://digitool.Library.McGill.CA:80/R/?func=dbin-jump-full&object_id=26296.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleJackson, Myles Wayne. „Goethe's law and order : nature and art in Elective Affinities“. Thesis, University of Cambridge, 1991. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.386168.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleNogues, Rosa. „The body of sexuation : feminist art practice in the 1990s“. Thesis, Kingston University, 2013. http://eprints.kingston.ac.uk/27842/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleMorton, Luise H. „Theories of three conceptual artists : a critique and comparison“. Virtual Press, 1985. http://liblink.bsu.edu/uhtbin/catkey/425069.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleBoda, Lena. „Facebook goes philosophy : Facebook - ett modernistiskt eller postmodernistiskt projekt?“ Thesis, Konstfack, Institutionen för Bildpedagogik (BI), 2009. http://urn.kb.se/resolve?urn=urn:nbn:se:konstfack:diva-515.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleFacebook is a social Internet community started in 2004 by Harward student Mark Zuckerberg and it has by now around 222 million users all over the world. How can one, by examining a few aspects of young peoples activity on the site, understand the act of identityshaping and the look at ourselfs, in two different ways? One connected to modernism and the other to postmodernism. The philosopher Hegel’s concept of recognition and Nietzsche’s notion of our will to power are related to the terms modernism and postmodernism, and the observations made in the interviews with 13 highschool students are interpreted with the help of them. The analysis treats four themes visible in the interviews. First, the frequent checking out on others’ activities, which is partly seen as fun, partly as useless. It can be understood as a way to get to know oneself throug reflection - or as a method to find out what is a successfull way of being. Second, the strong aim to show who one is, which could be interpreted as a need to try the own identity by showing it to others -or as a strategic demonstration of a consciously shaped image. Third, the attitude towards giving and getting comments, which vary between an unproblematic liking, and a rejection of the need for confirmation of one’s being. Fourth and finally, the difficulties with having one profile to be seen by all the ”friends”. This can be usefull if one is in search for a true identity that is so to speak already in oneself from the beginning. But this shaping of an image that is successfull among multiple viewers is also seen as a rather undramatic, or unproblematic, activity. The conclusion made is that Facebook stimulates as well a modernistic as a postmodernistic way of identity shaping. Its tools encourage the demonstration of the personality, but as it is very easy to play with these tools, an unrestrained designing of the identity is also possible. But the site wouldn’t really be interesting if it was considered a theatre scene – and it is quite clear that there is a wish to show who one really is, and that there is an idea about other persons having that kind of true selfs as well. But the caracter of the medium is such that people frequently suspect others to manipulate their identitys.
BI/Media
Welchman, Alistair. „'Wild above rule or art' : creation and critique“. Thesis, University of Warwick, 1995. http://wrap.warwick.ac.uk/4458/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleKauffman, Elizabeth. „Adrian Piper and Immanuel Kant toward a synthesis of art and philosophy /“. Cincinnati, Ohio : University of Cincinnati, 2009. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view.cgi?acc_num=ucin1259076570.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleKambalu, Samson. „Nyau philosophy : contemporary art and the problematic of the gift : a panegyric“. Thesis, University of the Arts London, 2016. http://ualresearchonline.arts.ac.uk/12398/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleMeloni, Gabriele. „Plato on establishing poetry as art“. Thesis, University of Edinburgh, 2014. http://hdl.handle.net/1842/9752.
Der volle Inhalt der Quelle