Dissertationen zum Thema „Naturalised Epistemology“
Geben Sie eine Quelle nach APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard und anderen Zitierweisen an
Machen Sie sich mit Top-35 Dissertationen für die Forschung zum Thema "Naturalised Epistemology" bekannt.
Neben jedem Werk im Literaturverzeichnis ist die Option "Zur Bibliographie hinzufügen" verfügbar. Nutzen Sie sie, wird Ihre bibliographische Angabe des gewählten Werkes nach der nötigen Zitierweise (APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver usw.) automatisch gestaltet.
Sie können auch den vollen Text der wissenschaftlichen Publikation im PDF-Format herunterladen und eine Online-Annotation der Arbeit lesen, wenn die relevanten Parameter in den Metadaten verfügbar sind.
Sehen Sie die Dissertationen für verschiedene Spezialgebieten durch und erstellen Sie Ihre Bibliographie auf korrekte Weise.
Inglis, S. „The form and scope of naturalised epistemology“. Thesis, University of Cambridge, 1998. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.604930.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleKrieger, Gordon S. F. „Connectionism, naturalized epistemology, and eliminative materialism“. Thesis, McGill University, 1993. http://digitool.Library.McGill.CA:80/R/?func=dbin-jump-full&object_id=68112.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleI present a review of the connectionist approach to psychological models that contrasts it with the classical symbolic approach, focusing on the nature of their respective representations. While defending the legitimacy of the connectionist approach, I find that its most useful application is as a basis for neuroscientific investigation.
Discussing connectionist psychology, I find it inconsistent with folk psychology and therefore consistent with eliminative materialism. I argue also for the naturalization of epistemology and thus for the relevance of psychology for epistemology. The conclusion of the essay is an outline of connectionist epistemology, which centres around two mathematical analyses of the global activity of connectionist networks; I argue that connectionist psychology leads to a version of epistemic pragmatism.
Freedman, Karyn L. „Naturalized epistemology and the construction of normativity“. Thesis, National Library of Canada = Bibliothèque nationale du Canada, 2001. http://www.collectionscanada.ca/obj/s4/f2/dsk3/ftp04/NQ59045.pdf.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleChristiansen, Jesse G. „Apriority in naturalized epistemology investigation into a modern defense /“. unrestricted, 2007. http://etd.gsu.edu/theses/available/etd-11272007-193136/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleTitle from file title page. George W. Rainbolt, committee chair; Jessica Berry, Steve Jacobson, committee members. Electronic text (43 p.) : digital, PDF file. Description based on contents viewed Jan 18, 2008. Includes bibliographical references (p. 43).
Christiansen, Jesse Giles. „Apriority in Naturalized Epistemology: Investigation into a Modern Defense“. Digital Archive @ GSU, 2007. http://digitalarchive.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/31.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleHundleby, Catherine. „Feminist standpoint theory as a form of naturalist epistemology“. Thesis, National Library of Canada = Bibliothèque nationale du Canada, 2001. http://www.collectionscanada.ca/obj/s4/f2/dsk3/ftp04/NQ58217.pdf.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleRoberts, Brenda. „Connectionism and the integration of error, applications in naturalized epistemology and minimal rationality“. Thesis, National Library of Canada = Bibliothèque nationale du Canada, 2000. http://www.collectionscanada.ca/obj/s4/f2/dsk2/ftp03/MQ47880.pdf.
Der volle Inhalt der QuellePenna-Forte, Marcelo do Amaral. „Iconografia cientifica : um estudo sobre as representações visuais na ciencia“. [s.n.], 2006. http://repositorio.unicamp.br/jspui/handle/REPOSIP/280453.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleTese (doutorado) - Universidade Estadual de Campinas, Instituto de Filosofia e Ciencias Humanas
Made available in DSpace on 2018-08-07T02:48:14Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 Penna-Forte_MarcelodoAmaral_D.pdf: 33078007 bytes, checksum: d5814e0c2de9c5cefde73b485db17b1e (MD5) Previous issue date: 2006
Resumo: A presente tese elabora um quadro geral para o estudo das representações visuais, tal como são utilizadas na atividade científica, na perspectiva de uma filosofia naturalista da ciência. Para tanto, é encaminhado um questionamento acerca das funções das representações visuais que passa pela consideração, orientada para este fim, da pertinência das análises funcionais, de uma noção adequada de representação e da caracterização da ciência como um sistema de representações. Conclui-se, finalmente, que as funções das representações visuais concernem à elaboração, ao desenvolvimento e, por vezes, à modificação da rede de similaridades que constitui a ciência
Abstract: This dissertation is concerned with the exposition of a naturalistic general framework for the study of visual representations as they are used in the scientific activity. It raises the question ci the role played by the visual representations in science. In order to do so, it argues for a functional analysis as a philosophical approach, suggests a suitable notion of representation, and describes science as a representational system. Finally, it concludes that visual representations can contribUte to the establishment, to the improvement, and to the revision of the network of similarities that constitutes science
Doutorado
Doutor em Filosofia
Guzman, Dahlia. „The Strategic Naturalism of Sandra Harding's Feminist Standpoint Epistemology: A Path Toward Epistemic Progress“. Scholar Commons, 2018. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/7626.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleLopes, Arthur Viana. „Três defesas do externalismo epistêmico“. Universidade Federal da Paraíba, 2010. http://tede.biblioteca.ufpb.br:8080/handle/tede/5689.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleCoordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior - CAPES
The purpose of this dissertation is to defend the position known in epistemic literature as epistemic externalism. This position essentially consists in the thesis that some of the features which determine when a belief is a case of knowledge or a case of justified belief are external to the epistemic agent, i.e., they are not internal states of the agent, nor need to be consciously accessed by him. We neither criticize any particular internalist theory, nor advocate a particular externalist theory. Instead, we discuss three different topics that work as a general motivation for adopting externalism. The option for these topics is guided by an interest in naturalistic epistemology and in recent discussions of epistemology. First, we discuss the use of cases the description of imaginary cases with the intent to emphasize the intuition of a particular proposition or to show the counterintuitive consequence of a theory in the debate between internalists and externalists. We try to provide a sort of psychological diagnosis of the use of this intuitive tool and argue that the literature on concepts psychology suggests an advantage for externalist theories. Second, we discuss the contextualist approach about the skeptical paradox and its relation to conceptual analysis. We argue that a semantic approach fails to solve the paradox and that the proper understanding of its origin, and also an invariantist rejection of the contextualist approach, provide a motivation to accept the externalist solution of the problem. At last, we deal with John Pollock s criticism against externalism the idea that a proper naturalistic theory of justification has to be internalist. We analyze whether his refutation really affects all form of externalism, particularly, process reliabilism. We present Pollock s procedural theory of epistemic norms, and discuss if the reasons he presents can actually refute process reliabilism. We claim that the reasons presented do not really put Pollock s project in an advantage.
A proposta deste trabalho é defender a posição conhecida na literatura epistemológica como externalismo epistêmico. O externalismo epistêmico consiste essencialmente na tese de que alguns dos fatores que determinam quando uma crença constitui um caso de conhecimento ou um caso de crença justificada são externos ao agente epistêmico, i.e., não são estados internos ao sujeito, nem precisam ser acessados conscientemente por ele. Nós não atacamos nenhuma teoria particular do internalismo, ou mesmo defendemos uma teoria externalista particular. Em lugar disto, discutimos três tópicos distintos que servem de motivação geral para a adoção do externalismo. A escolha destes tópicos é guiada pelo interesse em uma epistemologia naturalizada e em discussões recentes da epistemologia. Primeiro, nós discutimos a utilização da análise de casos a descrição de casos imaginários com a intenção de salientar a intuição de uma proposição particular ou mostrar a consequência antiintuitiva de uma teoria no debate entre internalistas e externalistas. Nós tentamos fornecer uma espécie de diagnóstico psicológico sobre o uso desta ferramenta intuitiva e argumentamos que a literatura em psicologia de conceitos sugere um favorecimento a teorias externalistas. Segundo, nós discutimos a abordagem contextualista sobre o paradoxo cético e sua relação com a análise conceitual. Nós argumentamos que uma abordagem semântica falha em resolver o paradoxo e que a compreensão adequada de sua origem, assim como uma rejeição invariantista da posição contextualista, fornece uma motivação para aceitarmos a solução externalista do problema. Por último, nós tratamos da crítica de John Pollock ao externalismo, que consiste justamente na ideia de que uma teoria de justificação naturalista adequada deve ser internalista. Nós analisamos se sua refutação realmente atinge toda forma de externalismo e, em particular, o confiabilismo de processo. Nós apresentamos a teoria procedimental de normas epistêmicas de Pollock e discutimos se as razões que ele apresenta podem realmente refutar o confiabilismo de processo. Nós defendemos que as razões que são apresentadas não colocam realmente o projeto de Pollock em vantagem.
Sousa, Claudiney Jose de 1976. „Hume e o naturalismo epistemológico = aspectos céticos e positivos de sua teoria da crença“. [s.n.], 2012. http://repositorio.unicamp.br/jspui/handle/REPOSIP/280060.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleTese (doutorado) - Universidade Estadual de Campinas, Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas
Made available in DSpace on 2018-08-19T18:05:36Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 Sousa_ClaudineyJosede_D.pdf: 2248193 bytes, checksum: 2086e31340227c88d3d49873a49aee2f (MD5) Previous issue date: 2012
Resumo: A adoção do modelo da ciência da natureza física, por parte de Hume, para a elaboração de seu projeto de uma ciência da natureza humana, permite ao autor construir um novo sistema de conhecimento, erigido sobre um fundamento inteiramente novo e seguro, mas exige, por outro lado, uma quase completa redefinição de velhos conceitos epistemológicos e uma revisão de teorias e concepções tradicionalmente aceitas em filosofia. Neste trabalho procuraremos avaliar esse audacioso empreendimento a partir do estudo da teoria humeana das crenças (mais particularmente, das crenças causais e da crença na existência dos corpos), destacando duas grandes concepções sobre a atitude do autor, a cética e a naturalista, quase sempre vistas como radicalmente diferentes e incompatíveis: i) por um lado os que tendem a enfatizar o lado negativo de sua filosofia, por entender que ele teria restringido o espaço tradicionalmente conferido à razão, como conceito normativo em filosofia, e exaltado conceitos desautorizados dessa tarefa, como hábito e imaginação (nesse grupo de autores estão, por exemplo, Thomas Reid, Thomas Hill Green e Bertrand Russell); ii) e por outro, os que realçam aspectos positivos e a subordinação da razão aos sentimentos para destacar o caráter irresistível e inevitável de nossas crenças naturais como critério para distinção e escolha entre crenças (a figura central deste segundo grupo de autores é Norman Kemp Smith). Veremos que no século XX o debate sobre a epistemologia humeana continua estimulador: John Wright, Galen Strawson e Edward Craig, são exemplos de uma tendência a conciliar as duas interpretações para uma melhor compreensão de sua epistemologia, mostrando que as duas posturas podem ser complementares ao invés de excludentes. Tendo examinado algumas das principais contribuições desse debate, posicionamos-nos em defesa da concepção segundo a qual o projeto de Hume pode ser visto como um trabalho precursor daquilo que hoje conhecemos como naturalismo epistemológico, embora, de uma forma geral, alguns autores que exploram essa perspectiva contemporânea, notadamente Quine, não reconheçam as contribuições de Hume. Acreditamos, porém, que o filósofo moderno teria fornecido, de forma pioneira, os parâmetros para uma visão científica e experimental sobre os processos e produtos cognitivos, de um modo inteiramente diferente daquele elaborado pela especulação filosófica apriorista. Sem ter que restringir a filosofia à mera extensão do fazer científico, defendemos que Hume se preocupa em preservar o caráter normativo desse empreendimento, como propuseram Kemp Smith, Louis Loeb, Michael Costa, entre outros. A base para a defesa dessa concepção estaria em sua reavaliação do estatuto epistemológico do conceito de crença que, embora seja um complemento essencial do conhecimento, contrapõe-se diretamente a este (conforme sugere Locke em seu Essay). Sendo assim, o tema central de nosso trabalho será a maneira como Hume procede a essa difícil tarefa de conciliar naturalismo e normatividade em sua teoria da crença, antecipando propostas muito conhecidas no século XX como o confiabilismo de Alvin Goldman, que analisaremos com o intuito de estabelecer pontos de contato entre o naturalismo pioneiro de Hume e a epistemologia contemporânea
Abstract: The adoption of natural science as a model for the project for a science of human nature led Hume to build a new system of knowledge, built, as he hoped, on an entirely new and secure foundation. But the implementation of this project would require an almost complete redefinition of old philosophical concepts, and a reappraisal of traditionally accepted philosophical theories. In the present work we attempt to evaluate this bold intellectual enterprise, taking as focal point Hume's theory of belief (and, more particularly, causal beliefs and belief in the existence of bodies), analyzing two major interpretative trends, the naturalistic and the skeptical, often seen as radically different and incompatible: i) To the latter belong those authors who tend to emphasize the negative side of Hume's philosophy by holding that he would have restricted the space traditionally accorded to reason as normative concept in philosophy, and that his theory of belief does not in fact have epistemological import, to the extent in which it is based on concepts such as habit and imagination (to this group belong, for instance, Thomas Reid, Thomas Hill Green and Bertrand Russell); ii) In the other, more recent interpretative trend, are those who seek to bring out the positive aspects of his theory, taking Hume's proposed subordination of reason to the sentiments as a way to highlight the inevitable and irresistible character of our natural beliefs, an not their epistemic devaluation. Norman Kemp Smith is the leading proponent of this position, taken up more recently by authors such as John Wright, Galen Strawson and Edward Craig. In fact, these authors seek to reconcile the two interpretations, by showing that the two positions can be complementary rather than exclusive. Having examined some of the major contributions of this debate, we argue that Hume's project can be seen as a pioneering work containing some central elements of the position now know as epistemological naturalism, although many of the philosophers who explore this contemporary perspective do not to acknowledge Hume's contributions. We believe, however, that in Hume we find guidelines for a scientific and experimental study of the cognitive processes and products which still retain much interest nowadays. Without reducing philosophy to a mere brach of natural science (as Quine famously proposed), Hume was, we argue, concerned to preserve the normative character of epistemology. The basis for the defense of this position is the reassessment of the epistemological status of the concept of belief. Thus, we try to show that the way in which Hume seeks to combine naturalism and normativity in his theory of belief bears resemblance to proposals such Alvin Goldman's reliabilism
Doutorado
Filosofia
Doutor em Filosofia
Girard, David. „Getting Beyond Good and Evil: Reconciling Naturalism and Skepticism in Nietzsche's Middle Period“. Thesis, Université d'Ottawa / University of Ottawa, 2016. http://hdl.handle.net/10393/34574.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleMelanson, William Jason. „Justified existential belief an investigation of the justifiability of believing in the existence of abstract mathematical objects /“. Columbus, Ohio : Ohio State University, 2006. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc%5Fnum=osu1140465070.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleAndrew, James B. „Hume, Skepticism, and the Search for Foundations“. University of Toledo / OhioLINK, 2014. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc_num=toledo1396628762.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleKirby, Christopher C. „Naturalism in the Philosophies of Dewey and Zhuangzi: The Live Creature and the Crooked Tree“. [Tampa, Fla] : University of South Florida, 2008. http://purl.fcla.edu/usf/dc/et/SFE0002645.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleWinters, Andrew Michael. „A Natural Case for Realism: Processes, Structures, and Laws“. Scholar Commons, 2015. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/5603.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleJones, Conner Douglas. „Secularism: A Measure of Explicit Agreement With Assumptions of Secularism (MEAAS)“. BYU ScholarsArchive, 2021. https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/etd/9225.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleRoure, Pascale. „L'écriture critique : Enjeux politiques, littéraires, épistémologiques, et philosophiques de la critique de la langue de Fritz Mauthner“. Thesis, Paris 4, 2015. http://www.theses.fr/2015PA040017.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleThis dissertation shows that Fritz Mauthner’s (1849-1923) famous “critique of language” should be understood as a unique mode and style of attack on the literary cultures and ideological codes of his time, characterized by the development of print media. His work was unique because, through his critiques of literary, journalistic, and scholarly writings, Mauthner developed a powerful form of immanent critique of language that engaged typical forms of thought in that period as it was embedded within the topoi of late nineteenth century Berlin practices of writing. By adopting and repeating the period’s chauvinistic and anti-Semitic clichés he exposed – through modes of irony and parody – their failures and anti-modernistic images. By contextualising all of Mauthner’s late nineteenth century writings, in particular his critical approaches to modern literature, this work reconstructs Mauthner’s unmasking of modernity’s constitutive paradoxes through the links that he revealed between literary, scholarly, and philosophical modernity
Saunders, Josiah Paul. „Kant's Departure from Hume's Moral Naturalism“. Thesis, University of Canterbury. Philosophy and Religious Studies, 2007. http://hdl.handle.net/10092/992.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleMiller, Jean Anne. „Naturalism & Objectivity: Methods and Meta-methods“. Diss., Virginia Tech, 2008. http://hdl.handle.net/10919/28329.
Der volle Inhalt der QuellePh. D.
Grino, Claire. „Corps, genre et nouvelles technologies biomédicales : reconfigurations antinaturalistes au sein des théories féministes“. Thesis, Paris 1, 2015. http://www.theses.fr/2015PA010523/document.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleThe biological materiality of the human body has become an object of unprecedented interventions through “new biomedical technologies” as medically assisted procreation, genetic tests, or hormonal contraception. This thesis interrogates the difficulties inherent to anti-naturalist approaches in order to address the biological dimension of sexed bodies. “One is not born a woman, one becomes one”, but is this also true for the body? The analytical frames of materialist or deconstructivist feminism cannot cease the modalities through which biomedical technologies invest the flesh. Do biomedical technologies make constructivist approaches obsolete through the revenge of a biological – hormonal, genetic, molecular – ground that tops the anatomical effects of socialization? Partisans of a feminist “material turn” seem to think so. After analyzing how the molecular biology revolution changes the very concept of nature in defining it as “life itself”, I offer an alternative interpretation by defining biomedical technologies as technologies of power that stem from a molecular biopolitics of gender. Instead of overturning constructivist perspectives, these new social mediations (residing on a new epistemic paradigm) help understanding a shift in what has been seen as the limits of gender. This shift creates unprecedented identities, experiences and subjectivities of gender. In exposing the coordinates of the biomedical apparatus, this comparative study between disciplinary techniques and molecular biopolitics of gender pleads for a renewed anti-naturalist critique that takes the form of a critique of technology in order to allow for a collective appropriation of biomedical technologies
CAMPELO, Wendel de Holanda Pereira. „A fundamentação da ciência da natureza humana de David Hume: uma epistemologia experimental“. Universidade Federal do Pará, 2013. http://repositorio.ufpa.br/jspui/handle/2011/5868.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleApproved for entry into archive by Ana Rosa Silva (arosa@ufpa.br) on 2014-10-10T12:34:53Z (GMT) No. of bitstreams: 2 license_rdf: 23898 bytes, checksum: e363e809996cf46ada20da1accfcd9c7 (MD5) Dissertacao_FundamentacaoCienciaNatureza.pdf: 1029893 bytes, checksum: fd37a796dbd85478ad6cbecd5914945c (MD5)
Made available in DSpace on 2014-10-10T12:34:53Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 2 license_rdf: 23898 bytes, checksum: e363e809996cf46ada20da1accfcd9c7 (MD5) Dissertacao_FundamentacaoCienciaNatureza.pdf: 1029893 bytes, checksum: fd37a796dbd85478ad6cbecd5914945c (MD5) Previous issue date: 2013
CAPES - Coordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior
A ciência da natureza humana é o projeto de Hume que concerne à toda sua filosofia –estética, ética, política, teoria do conhecimento, história, economia, filosofia da religião, etc. – coisa de que jamais poderíamos dar conta, dado a natureza do trabalho de mestrado. Por isso, contentamo-nos em falar apenas da fundamentação da ciência da natureza humana, referente à investigação acerca da origem das ideias e operações do entendimento, ou da investigação sobre as causas e os poderes ocultos do entendimento humano, com base no método experimental. A questão a que o nosso trabalho visa a lançar luz é precisamente esta: o que é uma ciência da natureza humana baseada no método experimental? Essa será, pois, a nossa tarefa adiante. Julgamos que, a partir de uma abordagem holística e científica da mente humana, Hume tenta explicar a natureza dos poderes ou faculdades intelectuais, sobretudo suas limitações e sua fragilidade. Sendo, pois, a base da ciência do homem o método experimental, o qual, por sua vez, tem o seu fundamento sólido na experiência e na observação, então é preciso perguntar: como e em que medida o uso de tal método tornou-se imprescindível à filosofia moral – isto é, às questões filosóficas de modo geral – e que tangem à ciência da natureza humana? Compreender isso é compreender a etapa inicial do projeto filosófico humiano, ou seja, o estudo do entendimento humano que, por sua vez, subdivide-se em dois momentos, a saber: (1) A ciência da mente, pela qual Hume mostra as limitações de nossas faculdades e poderes intelectuais e (2) o ceticismo que é, pois, as consequências desse estudo, a constatação da fragilidade e das limitações do entendimento humano. Nesse sentido, sentimo-nos livres para falar de algumas reflexões tanto do Tratado quanto da primeira Investigação, muitas vezes de maneira indistinta, tentando ressaltar que tais obras, quando comparadas, podem revelar o amadurecimento de um mesmo projeto filosófico que é a ciência da natureza humana. E este é exatamente o fio condutor de nossa pesquisa: como uma ciência da natureza humana é projetada por Hume e em que medida é possível falar do amadurecimento de seus propósitos? Com este exame inicial, poderemos responder alguns problemas acerca da visão pela qual Hume foi falsamente apontado como um cético radical. Apresentaremos por que a crítica sobre a sua “teoria das ideias” elaborada pelos filósofos do senso comum não considera importantes pontos de sua ciência da mente, gerando muitos mal-entendidos na posteridade. Em suma, no Capítulo 1 deste trabalho, examinaremos o que seria o projeto filosófico de Hume e, por meio desse exame, tentaremos apresentar, no Capítulo 2, as bases em que essa ciência da mente construída por Hume está sustentada. No capítulo 3, mostraremos que a interpretação cético-destrutiva da posteridade está equivocada, na medida em que desconsidera os meios que Hume encontrou à sua fundamentação da ciência da natureza humana.
The science of human nature is the Hume’s project concerning to all his philosophy – aesthesis, ethic, politic, theory of knowledge, history, economy, philosophy of religion etc. -; matter that we never could to account, because of the nature of a work of master’s degree. Hence, we just content ourselves to talk about to the foundation of science of human nature, concerning to the research about the origin of ideas and operations of understanding, or about the research regarding the causes and occult powers of human understanding, based on experimental method. The question that ours work seek to explain is closely this: What is a science of human nature based on experimental method? This one will, therefore, ours task from now on. We regard, from a holistic and scientific approach of human mind, Hume tries to explain the nature of powers or intellectual faculties, mainly its boundaries and weakness. Being, hence, the base of the science of man the experimental method that, in turn, has its solid foundation on the experience and observation; we must, then, to ask: how and to what extend the use of a such method became indispensable to the moral philosophy – that is, to the philosophical questions altogether – and that it touch on science of human nature? To know it is to know the initial step of philosophical Humean project, that is, the study of human understanding that, on the other hand, it is subdivided in two moments, viz, (1) the science of man, by which Hume shows the boundaries of ours faculties and intellectual powers and (2) the skepticism that is, then, the outcome this study, the finding of weakness and boundaries of human understand. In this sense, we feel free to talk about some account both of Treatise as first Enquiry, many times indistinctly, trying to emphasize that such works, when compared, can to reveal the maturation of a same philosophical project that is the science of human nature. And this is exactly this tread of ours research: how a science of human nature is projected by Hume and to what extend is possible to talk to maturation of its purposes? With this initial exam, we will be able to answer some problems concerning to the view by which Hume was appointed like radical skeptical. We will show why the critique regarding his “theory of ideas” taken by philosophers of common sense does not regard important points of his science of mind, generating many misunderstanding for posterity.In short, in the Chapter 1 of this work, we will examine what it was the Hume’s philosophical project and, by means of this exam, we will try to show, in the Chapter 2, the bases in which this science of mind constructed by Hume is sustained. In the Chapter 3, we will show that the interpretation skeptical-destructive of the posterity is misguided, in that it disregard the means found by Hume to his foundation of the science of human nature.
Dubreuil, Benoît. „Des hiérarchies de dominance au gourvernement des hommes: considérations naturalistes sur l'origine de l'Etat“. Doctoral thesis, Universite Libre de Bruxelles, 2007. http://hdl.handle.net/2013/ULB-DIPOT:oai:dipot.ulb.ac.be:2013/210708.
Der volle Inhalt der Quelle1) pourquoi des hommes, capables de culture, ont vécu pendant des centaines de milliers d'années dans des petits groupes de chasseurs-cueilleurs nomades et égalitaires
2) pourquoi l'apparition de sociétés de grande taille au cours du Néolithique s'est systématiquement accompagnée d'une différenciation sociale accrue, de l'apparition de hiérarchies de statuts et, éventuellement, de la centralisation du pouvoir politique.
La réponse proposée est que la taille des sociétés humaines est sensible à un effet de plafonnement. Ceci s'explique par le caractère conditionnel de la coopération humaine et par la mémoire limitée des humains en contexte social. Ce plafonnement de la taille des groupes ne peut être surmonté que si les humains créent des institutions qui permettent une division sociale du travail de sanction, ce qui à son tour dépend de l'émergence chez l'homme d'un langage et d'une théorie de l'esprit complexes. L'argument proposé est de type fonctionnaliste et vise à appuyer les théories en sciences sociales qui s'intéressent à l'évolution de la culture et des formes politiques.
Doctorat en philosophie et lettres, Orientation philosophie
info:eu-repo/semantics/nonPublished
O'Brien, Aaron John. „Friedrich Nietzsche’s "On the Genealogy of Morality" as History Serving Life“. Thesis, Université d'Ottawa / University of Ottawa, 2017. http://hdl.handle.net/10393/36198.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleLenka, Laxminarayan. „Against foundationalism: Towards Quine's naturalized epistemology“. Thesis, 1992. http://hdl.handle.net/2009/725.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleChen, Hsiao-yu, und 陳曉郁. „Normativity and Quine''s Naturalized Epistemology“. Thesis, 2003. http://ndltd.ncl.edu.tw/handle/45254251320337261900.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleTsai, Cheng-hung, und 蔡政宏. „The Naturalistic Approach to Epistemology--A Study of Quine's Naturalized Epistemology“. Thesis, 1998. http://ndltd.ncl.edu.tw/handle/77988188830765112547.
Der volle Inhalt der Quelle國立臺灣大學
哲學系
86
The aim of this thesis is to examine Quine's naturalized epistemology,investi-gating whether its adoption would repudiate the normative element in epistemo-logy. In his well-known essay "Epistemology Naturalized" of 1969, Quine arguesthat epistemology should be reconstructed as a branch of natural science, an empirical study of the relation between sensory stimulations and scientific theory formulations. There are three major objections that have been raised against Quine's argument and his approach to epistemology: (i)Quine's charact- erization of traditional epistemology is misconceived. (ii) Quine's recommedat-ion of naturalizing epistemology neglects the notion of epistemic justificati-on, and hence the evaluative strain in epistemology. (iii)Quine's naturalized epistemology, understood as a scientific study, does not and cannot response to the skeptical challenge to the very possibility of our knowledge of the ex-ternal world,and hence fails to be a normative study of knowledge. In this th-esis, I reconstruct Quine's argument for naturalizing epistemology within his systemic philosophy, and focus on Quine's holism and its application: Qui-ne relies on it in arguing against traditional epistemology (especially Carna-pian reductionist program), in supporting his thesis of underdetermination of physical theory and indeterminacy of translation, and in responding to radicalskepticism. It offers the key to an understanding of the normativity and scopeof Quine's naturalized epistemology. After analyzing three criticisms on Quin-e's naturalized epistemology, especially proposed by Harvey Siegel, Jaegwon Kim, Alvin Goldman, and Barry Stroud, I try to show that those critics miss the point because they do not appreciate the close connection between Quine's naturalistic approach and holistic approach to epistemology.
Bayer, Benjamin John. „Varieties of naturalized epistemology : criticisms and alternatives /“. 2007. http://gateway.proquest.com/openurl?url_ver=Z39.88-2004&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:dissertation&res_dat=xri:pqdiss&rft_dat=xri:pqdiss:3290175.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleSource: Dissertation Abstracts International, Volume: 68-11, Section: A, page: 4727. Adviser: Jonathan Waskan. Includes bibliographical references (leaves 256-269) Available on microfilm from Pro Quest Information and Learning.
Tsai, Pei-Ching, und 蔡佩青. „Questions of "Normativity" and "Justification" in Quinean Naturalized Epistemology“. Thesis, 2001. http://ndltd.ncl.edu.tw/handle/12708618419764739613.
Der volle Inhalt der Quelle國立臺灣大學
哲學研究所
89
Critics of Quine often regard his proposal of naturalizing philosophy as simply dismissing the normative dimension of epistemology, along with it the notion of justification. It is thus questionable whether the alleged successor program constitutes a suitable substitute. Quine, however, stresses that his naturalism does not repudiate the normative. He offers a means-ends approach to the explication of normativity. This account, as I shall try to show, does not really compete with other justificatory theories, but offers a background thesis in which we could deploy the investigation of the notion of justification. Within Quine’s own doctrine, we do perceive both a foundationalist as well as a coherentist perspective as to the question of evidential support. Foundationalism lies in his persistence on observation sentences--being conditioned outright to some ranges of stimulation--as the checkpoint of science, while coherentism manifests in his holistic consideration. It is nonetheless a tremendous hard work to offer a streamlined account conjoining these two parts. The problem occurs when we consider how the purported empirical basis, i.e. stimulation, lends support to our overall theory of the world. The evidential relation, as Davidson rightly criticizes, remains obscure. Quine’s overall conception has a relish of pragmatism, owing primarily to his naturalistic orientation. It remains to be discussed whether pragmatic consideration could play any role in reconciling, or in cutting through, the tension and debate between foundationalism and coherentism.
Williams, Robert A. „Peircean Naturalism“. Diss., 2013. http://hdl.handle.net/10161/7217.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleNaturalism faces problems caused by a lack of agreement about whether there is or can be a meaningful and useful conception of naturalism as a general research position. Without a widely agreed upon account of what naturalism in general amounts to there is no clear and definitive way to adjudicate disputes as to what is consistent with naturalism; the absence of such an account also makes it impossible for specific projects in naturalistic inquiry to take guidance from naturalism in general. In the following, I develop a determinate account of naturalism in general, which I think could find acceptance among naturalists because it accounts for many of the features commonly associated with naturalism. To do this, I first lay out the problem to be solved, express its importance, and explain what a solution to the problem would involve. I then make appeal to an account of naturalism developed by Penelope Maddy and use this account to show that the published and unpublished work of Charles Sanders Peirce offers, prima facie, a more determinate account of naturalism than is commonly recognized and that goes beyond the account given by Maddy. With this Peircean account developed, I then measure it against the criteria I develop and conclude that a Pericean account of naturalism does promise to adjudicate various disputes in the naturalism literature and to offer guidance to the development and application of specific projects in naturalistic inquiry.
Dissertation
Mashburn, Emmett Frank. „On Alvin Plantinga’s Evolutionary Argument against Naturalism“. 2010. http://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss/824.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleRoberts, Brenda. „Connectionism and the integration of error : applications in naturalized epistemology and minimal rationality“. Thesis, 1999. http://spectrum.library.concordia.ca/938/1/MQ47880.pdf.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleBar, Roi. „Metascience as Self-Knowledge“. 2016. https://ul.qucosa.de/id/qucosa%3A15977.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleCushing, Jeremy. „Self-knowledge in a natural world“. 2012. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations/AAI3498338.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleMoghaddam, Soroush. „Confronting the Normativity Objection: W.V. Quine’s Engineering Model and Michael A. Bishop and J.D. Trout’s Strategic Reliabilism“. Thesis, 2013. http://hdl.handle.net/1828/4915.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleGraduate
0422
0621
soushi@gmail.com