Inhaltsverzeichnis
Auswahl der wissenschaftlichen Literatur zum Thema „Leibniz“
Geben Sie eine Quelle nach APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard und anderen Zitierweisen an
Machen Sie sich mit den Listen der aktuellen Artikel, Bücher, Dissertationen, Berichten und anderer wissenschaftlichen Quellen zum Thema "Leibniz" bekannt.
Neben jedem Werk im Literaturverzeichnis ist die Option "Zur Bibliographie hinzufügen" verfügbar. Nutzen Sie sie, wird Ihre bibliographische Angabe des gewählten Werkes nach der nötigen Zitierweise (APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver usw.) automatisch gestaltet.
Sie können auch den vollen Text der wissenschaftlichen Publikation im PDF-Format herunterladen und eine Online-Annotation der Arbeit lesen, wenn die relevanten Parameter in den Metadaten verfügbar sind.
Zeitschriftenartikel zum Thema "Leibniz"
Liu, Linlin, und Shuanhong Wang. „The construction of Hom-Leibniz H-pseudoalgebras“. Filomat 36, Nr. 8 (2022): 2617–36. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/fil2208617l.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleDella Rocca, Michael. „A New Defense of the Principle of Sufficient Reason“. Journal of Philosophy 120, Nr. 4 (2023): 220–27. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/jphil202312049.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleLodge, Paul. „Leibniz’s Philosophical Dream of Rational and Intuitive Enlightenment“. Dialogue and Universalism 32, Nr. 1 (2022): 203–19. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/du202232112.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleMovahedi, Hamed. „A Deleuzian Dialogue between Leibniz and Ruyer: Monads, Absolute Survey and Life“. Deleuze and Guattari Studies 18, Nr. 2 (Mai 2024): 246–76. http://dx.doi.org/10.3366/dlgs.2024.0553.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleWerther, David. „Leibniz and the Possibility of God's Existence“. Religious Studies 32, Nr. 1 (März 1996): 37–48. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0034412500024057.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleZARIŅŠ, VALTERS. „FREEDOM AS THE MAIN PROBLEM OF PHILOSOPHY GÜNTHER NEUMANN DER FREIHEITSBEGRIFF BEI GOTTFRIED WILHELM LEIBNIZ UND MARTIN HEIDEGGER. PHILOSOPHISCHE SCHRIFTEN, BAND 9. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 2019 ISBN 978-3-428-15537-8 HEIDEGGER UND LEIBNIZ. MIT EINEM GELEITWORT VON FRIEDRICH-WILHELM VON HERRMANN (DAS DENKEN MARTIN HEIDEGGERS II 2 HRSG. VON HANS-CHRISTIAN GÜNTHER). Traugott Bautz Verlag, Nordhausen, 2020 ISBN 978-3-95948-493-0“. HORIZON / Fenomenologicheskie issledovanija/ STUDIEN ZUR PHÄNOMENOLOGIE / STUDIES IN PHENOMENOLOGY / ÉTUDES PHÉNOMÉNOLOGIQUES 10, Nr. 1 (2021): 305–11. http://dx.doi.org/10.21638/2226-5260-2021-10-1-305-311.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleGarber, Daniel. „Leibniz On Form and Matter“. Early Science and Medicine 2, Nr. 3 (1997): 326–51. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/157338297x00177.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleKrivenko, Ekaterina Yahyaoui. „Space, Law, and Justice in Leibniz: Leibniz as a Theorist of Spatial Justice“. Law and History Review 36, Nr. 4 (10.09.2018): 891–914. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0738248018000391.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleSolomon, Graham. „Leibniz and Topological Equivalence“. Dialogue 32, Nr. 4 (1993): 721–24. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0012217300011355.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleMalek, Abdul. „KEPLER – NEWTON – LEIBNIZ – HEGEL“. JOURNAL OF ADVANCES IN PHYSICS 19 (15.09.2021): 221–23. http://dx.doi.org/10.24297/jap.v19i.9106.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleDissertationen zum Thema "Leibniz"
Hogan, Adam D. „Leibniz Did Not State Leibniz's Law“. Ohio University / OhioLINK, 2014. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc_num=ohiou1397054389.
Der volle Inhalt der QuellePoças, Jacinta Rodrigues. „Leibniz hierarchy“. Master's thesis, Universidade de Aveiro, 2009. http://hdl.handle.net/10773/2916.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleA Lógica Algébrica Abstracta estuda o processo pelo qual uma classe de álgebras pode ser associada a uma lógica. Nesta dissertação, analisamos este processo agrupando lógicas partilhando certas propriedades em classes. O conceito central neste estudo é a congruência de Leibniz que assume o papel desempenhado pela equivalência no processo tradicional de Lindenbaum- Tarski. Apresentamos uma hierarquia entre essas classes que é designada por hierarquia de Leibniz, caracterizando as lógicas de cada classe por propriedades meta-lógicas, por exemplo propriedades do operador de Leibniz. Estudamos também a recente abordagem comportamental que usa lógicas multigénero, lógica equacional comportamental e, consequentemente, uma versão comportamental do operador de Leibniz. Neste contexto, apresentamos alguns exemplos, aos quais aplicamos esta nova teoria, capturando alguns fenómenos de algebrização que não era possível formalizar com a abordagem standard. ABSTRACT: Abstract Algebraic logic studies the process by which a class of algebras can be associated with a logic. In this dissertation, we analyse this process by grouping logics sharing certain properties into classes. The central concept in this study is the Leibniz Congruence that assumes the role developed by the equivalence in the traditional Lindenbaum-Tarski process. We show a hierarchy between these classes, designated by Leibniz hierarchy, by characterizing logics in each class by meta-logical properties, for example properties of the Leibniz operator. We also study a recent behavioral approach which uses many-sorted logics, behavioral equational logic and, consequently, a behavioral version of the Leibniz operator. In this context, we provide some examples, to which we apply this new theory, capturing some phenomena of algebraization that are not possible to formalize using the standard approach.
Oudom, Jean-Michel. „Cogèbres de Leibniz duales et homologie des algèbres de Leibniz“. Montpellier 2, 1997. http://www.theses.fr/1997MON20015.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleDavillé, Louis. „Leibniz historien : essai sur l'activité et la méthode historiques de Leibniz /“. Darmstatd : Scientia Verlag AAlen, 1986. http://catalogue.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/cb37472128m.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleSchneider, Ulrich Johannes. „Leibniz und der Eklektizismus“. Universitätsbibliothek Leipzig, 2014. http://nbn-resolving.de/urn:nbn:de:bsz:15-qucosa-149007.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleLacerda, Tessa Moura. „A expressão em Leibniz“. Universidade de São Paulo, 2006. http://www.teses.usp.br/teses/disponiveis/8/8133/tde-30012008-112330/.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleExpression is one of the most important notions of Leibniz\'s philosophy. The philosopher addresses it directly in some texts, however, more than an object of analysis, the notion of expression organizes and makes reflections about Leibnizian theology, ontology and epistemology converge. Leibniz is not the first to deal with expression; the originality of his approach lies in a mathematical interpretation of expression, which makes it possible to define it as an analogy of relations between expression and expresser. One thing expresses another, says Leibniz, when there is a regular and reciprocal correspondence between the two, or between what can be said of one and the other. Accordingly, expression presupposes analogy and harmony. Having defined the relation of expression in these terms, it is possible, at the theological or metaphysical level, to explain how God expresses himself in simple, absolute and infinite forms, which express themselves in general systems of phenomena or possible worlds, which are expressed in individual notions and do not exist outside them. At the ontological level, we shall say that individuals express God as a cause and the world which they are part of. These individuals, in turn, express themselves as phenomena that are unified by tho ught as bodies. The relation that defines the bodies and the relation between bodies express the ideal relations that individual substances maintain amongst themselves, the physical order expresses the metaphysical order. At the epistemological level, we shall say that our ideas express the ideas of God; we agree with God in the same relations. But to know these relations, the present expression in an idea has to be developed. The classification of ideas in Leibniz presupposes this progressive development that takes place as a gradual analysis: the ideas may be obscure or clear, these ones confused or distinct, these ones inadequate or adequate, and the adequate ideas may be the object of a blind or symbolic knowledge and of an intuitive knowledge, very rare. The scope of the notion of expression makes it possible to put heterogeneous orders into a relation and to show the convergence and similarity of different things. In this measure, we can relate such different things as characters and thoughts, hence Leibniz\'s quest for a universal language or Characteristic.
Schneider, Ulrich Johannes. „Leibniz’ Revolution des Bibliothekskatalogs“. SLUB Dresden, 2016. https://slub.qucosa.de/id/qucosa%3A7776.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleSchneider, Ulrich Johannes. „Leibniz und der Eklektizismus“. de Gruyter, 2002. https://ul.qucosa.de/id/qucosa%3A12761.
Der volle Inhalt der QuellePlanas-Bielsa, Victor. „Leibniz manifolds and Lyapunov“. Nice, 2004. http://www.theses.fr/2004NICE4027.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleThe first part of this thesis shows that various relevant dynamical system scan be described as vector fields associated to smooth functions vi a bracket that defines what we call a Leibniz structure. Several examples can be described using this construction that generalises the standard Poisson brackets. The symmetries of these systems and the associated reduction in Leibniz and almost Poisson manifolds are described in detail. The second part of this thesis includes results centred around the nonlinear stability of equilibrium in Poisson dynamical systems. We prove an energy-Casimir type sufficient condition for stability that uses function (not necessary conserved) that takes into account certain asymptotically stable behaviour that may occur in the Poisson category. We discussed also two situations in which the use of Casimir functions in stability is equivalent to the topological methods introduced by Patrick et al
Feeney, Thomas D. „Leibniz on Metaphysical Perfection“. Thesis, Yale University, 2017. http://pqdtopen.proquest.com/#viewpdf?dispub=10584944.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleLeibniz makes substantive use of harmony and metaphysical perfection, but he very rarely offers more than a brief gloss in direct explanation of these terms. I argue that they name the same fundamental property. The definition of metaphysical perfection (hereafter, "perfection") as unity-in-variety misleads if taken as a reduction of perfection to separately necessary and jointly sufficient conditions for anything to enjoy perfection. The definition of harmony in terms of intelligibility leads to the same underlying notion, for intelligibility is defined in terms of unity and variety.
Chapter 1 introduces the tension between Leibniz's substantive use of perfection and his demand that it meet a high standard of intelligibility. Chapter 2 argues that there is no satisfactory account of compossibility in the literature because each of the viable proposals misunderstands the role of perfection. The current dispute rests in a disagreement about the best reductive account of perfection: either to sheer variety, or to variety and unity as independently intelligible but inversely proportional criteria for perfection. Either way, incompossibility relations become externally applied limits on God's will to maximize the variety of existing substances. Leibniz rejects all such external limits. I propose a new solution, in which two possibles are compossible if and only if they are jointly thinkable, that is, if they are members of an ideal unity. This involves a distinction between the variety that does contribute to unity and the variety that does not—and this distinction requires that we already have some notion of perfection prior to the appeal to variety.
Chapter 3 develops this account of perfection and incompossibility further, by introducing another puzzle God aims to create the most perfect world, but worlds are aggregates and aggregates seem to rank too low in Leibniz's ontology to explain God's aim. What is the world that God would care for it? God, being wise, does not and would not will multiple times in creating. Rather, God creates multiple substances through a single act of will. Acts of creative will, though, are individuated by the agent's concept of the object. This suggests that groups of substances are unified into worlds by God's intellect thinking of their many essences under a single idea. This is Leibniz's limited Spinozism: he is a metaphysical atomist about existing things, but a holist about the ideal and its value.
Chapters 4 and 5 tell the story of how Leibniz came to these views. The narrative is helpful in part because it sheds some light on Leibniz's motivations. Also, I argue that the mistakes common to recent approaches to compossibility have textual support only from premature versions of Leibniz's account of perfection, versions Leibniz rejected in part because they generate the problems discussed in Chapters 2 and 3.
Chapter 4 explores Leibniz's transition to philosophical maturity in the later 167os. He gave priority to the divine intellect throughout his career, but in the Paris Period, he left no work for the will at all: to exist is to be harmonious, and the existence of finite things depends directly on the divine intellect. This theory had theodicean advantages, but it also led to a necessitarianism just as absolute as Spinoza's. After studying Spinoza and leaving Paris, Leibniz placed the divine will between existence and harmony, or perfection. Perfection and harmony were now associated with God's ideas; coming to exist required, in addition, an act of God's will.
Having associated harmony with the possibles in God's mind, Leibniz now needed to explain why God does not maximize perfection by creating every substance. Chapter 5 deals with the gradual development after 1678, as Leibniz worked out how to determine the joint value of many independent substances. Just as previously he had separated existence from harmony while retaining a close connection between the two, the mature Leibniz distinguished harmony from the possible substances in God's mind. Harmony and perfection, on this final account, belong even to aggregates, which count as unities thanks only to their relation to a mind. With this in hand, Leibniz was finally in a position to argue that God leaves some possibles uncreated in order the maximize the perfection of what God does create.
Leibniz defended his commitment to a harmoniously limited, intelligible world by gradually distinguishing perfection from existence and from substantiality. Likewise, we profit by distinguishing Leibnizian perfection from (apparently) more accessible notions.
Bücher zum Thema "Leibniz"
Jolley, Nicholas. Leibniz. second edition. | New York: Routledge, 2019. |: Routledge, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780429422775.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleBouveresse, Renée. Leibniz. Paris: Presses universitaires de France, 1994.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle findenJolley, Nicholas. Leibniz. London: Routledge, 2005.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle finden1951-, Wilson Catherine, Hrsg. Leibniz. Aldershot, Hants, England: Dartmouth, Ashgate ; Burlington, Vt., 2001.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle findenHessel, Daalder, Hrsg. Leibniz. Rotterdam: Lemniscaat, 2001.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle findenmissing], [name. On Leibniz. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press, 2003.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle finden1907-, Müller Kurt, Heinekamp Albert und Mertens Marlen, Hrsg. Leibniz-Bibliographie.: Die Literatur über Leibniz, 1981-1990. Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann, 1996.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle findenFaak, Margot. Leibniz als Reichshofrat. Herausgegeben von Wenchao Li. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer Berlin Heidelberg, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-48390-9.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleDingel, Irene, Michael Kempe und Wenchao Li, Hrsg. Leibniz in Mainz. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.13109/9783666571275.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleCristin, Renato. Heidegger and Leibniz. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 1998. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9032-7.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleBuchteile zum Thema "Leibniz"
Anglin, W. S., und J. Lambek. „Leibniz“. In The Heritage of Thales, 159–62. New York, NY: Springer New York, 1995. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4612-0803-7_30.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleAnglin, W. S. „Leibniz“. In Mathematics: A Concise History and Philosophy, 181–84. New York, NY: Springer New York, 1994. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4612-0875-4_31.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleSeager, William. „Leibniz“. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Science, 224–28. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishers Ltd, 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781405164481.ch34.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleMerchant, Carolyn. „Leibniz*“. In Science and Nature, 68–87. New York, NY : Routledge, 2017.: Routledge, 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9781315111988-7.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleLook, Brandon C. „Kant’s Leibniz“. In Leibniz and Kant, 1–26. Oxford University Press, 2021. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780199606368.003.0001.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleTissandier, Alex. „Leibniz and Expression“. In Affirming Divergence, 40–57. Edinburgh University Press, 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.3366/edinburgh/9781474417747.003.0003.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleRutherford, Donald. „Leibniz as Idealist“. In Oxford Studies In Early Modern Philosophy, 141–90. Oxford University PressOxford, 2008. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780199550401.003.0005.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleNewlands, Samuel. „Leibniz on Modality“. In Modality, 118–43. Oxford University PressNew York, 2024. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190089856.003.0006.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleNachtomy, Ohad. „Leibniz in Paris“. In Living Mirrors, 35–62. Oxford University Press, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190907327.003.0003.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleRodriguez-Pereyra, Gonzalo. „Leibniz“. In The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics, 109–18. Routledge, 2009. http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780203879306-13.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleKonferenzberichte zum Thema "Leibniz"
Wu, Zhixiang. „Leibniz conformal algebras of rank three“. In The Eighth China–Japan–Korea International Symposium on Ring Theory. WORLD SCIENTIFIC, 2021. http://dx.doi.org/10.1142/9789811230295_0014.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleWADE, AISSA. „ON SOME PROPERTIES OF LEIBNIZ ALGEBROIDS“. In Infinite Dimensional Lie Groups in Geometry and Representation Theory. WORLD SCIENTIFIC, 2002. http://dx.doi.org/10.1142/9789812777089_0005.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleRikhsiboev, Ikrom M., und Isamiddin S. Rakhimov. „Classification of three dimensional complex Leibniz algebras“. In THE 5TH INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON RESEARCH AND EDUCATION IN MATHEMATICS: ICREM5. AIP, 2012. http://dx.doi.org/10.1063/1.4724168.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleHu, Naihong, Dong Liu und Linsheng Zhu. „Leibniz Superalgebras Graded by Finite Root Systems“. In Proceedings of the International Conference. WORLD SCIENTIFIC, 2012. http://dx.doi.org/10.1142/9789814365123_0003.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleAlmutari, Hassan, und Abd Ghafur Ahmad. „Quasi-centroids of four dimensional Leibniz algebras“. In THE 2018 UKM FST POSTGRADUATE COLLOQUIUM: Proceedings of the Universiti Kebangsaan Malaysia, Faculty of Science and Technology 2018 Postgraduate Colloquium. AIP Publishing, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.1063/1.5111215.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleSo, Hiroto. „Leibniz rule, locality and supersymmetry on lattice“. In The 30th International Symposium on Lattice Field Theory. Trieste, Italy: Sissa Medialab, 2012. http://dx.doi.org/10.22323/1.164.0231.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleHolland, L. „REID’S CRITIQUE OF LEIBNIZ NOTION OF FREE AGENCY“. In 2nd International Academic Conference on Humanities and Social Science. Acavent, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.33422/2iachss.2019.02.52.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleKasim, Suzila Mohd, Isamiddin S. Rakhimov und Sharifah Kartini Said Husain. „Isomorphism classes of 10-dimensional filiform Leibniz algebras“. In PROCEEDINGS OF THE 3RD INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES. AIP Publishing LLC, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.1063/1.4882563.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleHusain, Sh K. Said, I. S. Rakhimov und W. Basri. „Centroids and derivations of low-dimensional Leibniz algebra“. In PROCEEDINGS OF THE 24TH NATIONAL SYMPOSIUM ON MATHEMATICAL SCIENCES: Mathematical Sciences Exploration for the Universal Preservation. Author(s), 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1063/1.4995838.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleBusch, Steffen, Christian Koetsier, Jeldrik Axmann und Claus Brenner. „LUMPI: The Leibniz University Multi-Perspective Intersection Dataset“. In 2022 IEEE Intelligent Vehicles Symposium (IV). IEEE, 2022. http://dx.doi.org/10.1109/iv51971.2022.9827157.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleBerichte der Organisationen zum Thema "Leibniz"
Pradilla, Magdalena, John Alexander Rico Franco und Evelyn Garnica Estrada. El cálculo y las máquinas para calcular de Leibniz, Boole y Babbage. Corporación Universitaria Republicana, Oktober 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.21017/cont.virt.2020.s1.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleSilberstein, Marian. Application of a Generalized Leibniz Rule for Calculating Electromagnetic Fields within Continuous Source Regions. Fort Belvoir, VA: Defense Technical Information Center, Januar 1989. http://dx.doi.org/10.21236/ada212470.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleSchreiber, Verena. Lokale Präventionsgremien in Deutschland. Goethe-Universität, Institut für Humangeographie, Mai 2007. http://dx.doi.org/10.21248/gups.1092.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleJohnson, Joshua B., J. Edward Gates und W. Mark Ford. Notes on foraging activity of female Myotis leibii in Maryland. Newtown Square, PA: U.S. Department of Agriculture, Forest Service, Northern Research Station, 2009. http://dx.doi.org/10.2737/nrs-rp-8.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleRoby, Piper, Andrew Taylor, Gregg Janos und Will Seiter. New River Gorge Cliff Line Bat Inventory Survey. National Park Service, 2024. http://dx.doi.org/10.36967/2303814.
Der volle Inhalt der Quelle