Um die anderen Arten von Veröffentlichungen zu diesem Thema anzuzeigen, folgen Sie diesem Link: Kant`s critique of taste.

Zeitschriftenartikel zum Thema „Kant`s critique of taste“

Geben Sie eine Quelle nach APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard und anderen Zitierweisen an

Wählen Sie eine Art der Quelle aus:

Machen Sie sich mit Top-50 Zeitschriftenartikel für die Forschung zum Thema "Kant`s critique of taste" bekannt.

Neben jedem Werk im Literaturverzeichnis ist die Option "Zur Bibliographie hinzufügen" verfügbar. Nutzen Sie sie, wird Ihre bibliographische Angabe des gewählten Werkes nach der nötigen Zitierweise (APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver usw.) automatisch gestaltet.

Sie können auch den vollen Text der wissenschaftlichen Publikation im PDF-Format herunterladen und eine Online-Annotation der Arbeit lesen, wenn die relevanten Parameter in den Metadaten verfügbar sind.

Sehen Sie die Zeitschriftenartikel für verschiedene Spezialgebieten durch und erstellen Sie Ihre Bibliographie auf korrekte Weise.

1

Grubor, Nebojsa. "Hermeneutics of taste Gadamer’s critique of Kant’s aesthetics in truth and method." Theoria, Beograd 59, no. 3 (2016): 23–33. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/theo1603023g.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
The Article explains Gadamer?s critique of Kant?s aesthetics in Truth and Method (1960). The paper first examines basics characteristics of Kant?s foundation of modern aesthetics (I). This is followed by consideration Gadamer?s interpretations of the process of the subjectivization of aesthetics in Kant?s Third Critique (II). Finally, it considers critique of abstraction aesthetic consciousness and conception of aesthetic differentiation as Gadamer?s attempt to through analysis of Kant?s theory of taste complete its own hermeneutics of art (III).
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
2

Popovic, Una. "The problem of aesthetic judgment: Perspectives of aesthetics." Filozofija i drustvo 24, no. 3 (2013): 5–22. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/fid1303005p.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
This paper deals with the interpretation of Kant?s Critique of Judgment from the perspective of aesthetics. Our aim here is to show the immanent relationship between the two main motifs of this work: the analysis of traditional aesthetic problems, such as beauty and taste, on the one hand, and the systematical thinking, philosophy, and Kant?s critical project, on the other. This interpretation is developed in consideration of the prob?lem of aesthetics as a philosophical discipline, within which, for each of the motifs of Kant?s third critique it is shown how it redefines aesthetic into philos
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
3

Pereira, Geraldo Adriano Emery. "A LEITURA ARENDTIANA DA FACULDADE DO JUÍZO KANTIANA." Síntese: Revista de Filosofia 38, no. 121 (2011): 183. http://dx.doi.org/10.20911/21769389v38n121p183-210/2011.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
Este texto detém-se sobre um tema polêmico no contexto da obra da filósofa Hannah Arendt – a faculdade do juízo. A análise gira em torno da demonstração do modo como as peculiaridades da crítica do gosto kantiana são apropriadas por Arendt, numa leitura política desta faculdade. O artigo ensaia num primeiro momento uma apresentação do juízo de gosto; em seguida aponta os elementos que são apropriados por Arendt e sua leitura política. Deste modo se apresenta uma justificativa teórica para a apropriação arendtiana da faculdade do juízo de gosto kantiana, mostrando que, apesar de seu caráter “su
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
4

Sweet, Kristi. "Reflection: Its Structure and Meaning in Kant's Judgements of Taste." Kantian Review 14, no. 1 (2009): 53–80. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1369415400001345.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
When Kant announces in a letter to Reinhold that he has discovered a new domain of a priori principles, he situates these principles in a ‘faculty of feeling pleasure and displeasure’ (Zammito 1992: 47). And it is indeed in his Critique of Aesthetic Judgement, named in this letter the Critique of Taste, that we find his elucidation of the relation of the principle of purposiveness to the feeling of pleasure. The kinds of judgements in which our feelings are evaluated in accordance with a principle are what Kant names reflective judgements. And while reflective judgements emerge in the third Cr
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
5

Dumler-Winckler, Emily. "Romanticism as Modern Re-Enchantment: Burke, Kant, and Emerson on Religious Taste." Journal for the History of Modern Theology / Zeitschrift für Neuere Theologiegeschichte 22, no. 1 (2015): 1–22. http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/znth-2015-1001.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
AbstractThis essay traces the contours of a trans-Atlantic Romantic legacy of aesthetic, moral and religious taste from its inception in Edmund Burke, through its modifications by Immanuel Kant, to its culmination in Ralph Waldo Emerson’s Divinity School Address. In A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and the Beautiful Burke suggests that religious experience is an aspect of aesthetic and moral taste. Immanuel Kant follows suit in the Critique of Judgment, offering a distinct account of religious taste. Emerson alludes to yet significantly refines aspects of bot
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
6

Rueger, Alexander. "Pleasure and Purpose in Kant’s Theory of Taste." Kant-Studien 109, no. 1 (2018): 101–23. http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/kant-2018-0003.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
Abstract: In the Critique of Judgment Kant repeatedly points out that it is only the pleasure of taste that reveals to us the need to introduce a third faculty of the mind with its own a priori principle. In order to elucidate this claim I discuss two general principles about pleasure that Kant presents, the transcendental definition of pleasure from § 10 and the principle from the Introduction that connects pleasure with the achievement of an aim. Precursors of these principles had been employed by Kant and others in empirical psychology. But how can such principles of empirical psychology be
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
7

Otabe, Tanehisa. "An Iroquois in Paris and a Crusoe on a Desert Island: Kant’s Aesthetics and the Process of Civilization." Culture and Dialogue 6, no. 1 (2018): 35–50. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/24683949-12340040.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
Abstract In section 2 of Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790) Immanuel Kant refers to the Iroquois sachem declaring that what pleased him in Paris were cook-shops, not palaces. For Kant the sachem seems to be a barbarian ensnared by his appetite and incapable of disinterested pleasure. This essay, however, argues first that Kant, extracting this episode from “The History of New France” (1744) written by French Jesuit missionary Charlevoix, tacitly advocates the idea of the noble savage, thereby giving the Iroquois sachem the function of criticizing a luxurious civilization. Second, the ess
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
8

Allison, Henry E. "Beauty and Duty in Kant's Critique of Judgement." Kantian Review 1 (March 1997): 53–81. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1369415400000066.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
At the end of §40 of the Critique of Judgement, after a discussion of the sensus communis and its connection with taste, Kant writes:If we could assume that the mere universal communicability as such of our feeling must already carry with it an interest for us (something we are, however, not justified in inferring from the character of a merely reflective power of judgment), then we could explain how it is that we require from everyone as a duty, as it were (gleichsam), the feeling in a judgment of taste. (5: 296; 162)
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
9

Hahmann, Andree. "Kant’s Critical Argument(s) for Immortality Reassessed." Kant Yearbook 10, no. 1 (2018): 19–41. http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/kantyb-2018-0002.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
AbstractKant’s postulate of the immortality of the soul has received strikingly little attention among Kant scholars, and only very few have regarded it positively. This is not surprising given the numerous problems associated with his argument. However, it is not the only argument for immortality that Kant offers in his critical philosophy. There is also a second argument that differs from the one furnished in the Second Critique and can be found both in the Critique of Pure Reason and later texts from the 1790s. Kant also addresses here many of the problems that interpreters have found with
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
10

Romo, Vicente De Haro. "Reseña de Kant´s Critique of Spinoza, de O. Boehm." Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía, no. 48 (June 8, 2015): 265. http://dx.doi.org/10.21555/top.v0i48.683.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
En esta reseña, resumo el contenido y expongo la estructura del libro de Omri Boehm, Kant´s Critique of Spinoza, y evalúo los argumentos del autor para tratar de mostrar que en la Crítica de la razón pura el interlocutor de Kant es el filósofo judío.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
11

Lukic, Aleksandar. "Kant’s critique of pure reason and the dogmatism of metaphysics." Theoria, Beograd 64, no. 1 (2021): 23–30. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/theo2101023l.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
In this paper, the author explores Kant?s Copernican revolution that departs from philosophical tradition. Kant challenges a view that the existence of the world (with the totality of all laws that hold in it) is independent of the knower. In view of that, the main focus is on Kant?s analysis of the meaning of a priori knowledge and the critique of old (dogmatic) metaphysics. The aim of this critique, however, was not the dismissal of metaphysics as such, but rather the transcendental foundation of a new one.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
12

Dumouchel, Daniel. "Kant et l'expérience esthétique de la liberté." Dialogue 35, no. 3 (1996): 571–92. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0012217300008878.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
Kant and the Experience of Freedom rassemble les articles de Paul Guyer consacrés à l'esthétique de Kant depuis 1982 et un certain nombre de textes inédits qui vont jusqu'à 1991. Il s'agira certainement d'un jalon important dans l'interprétation de l'esthétique de Kant et des questions philosophiques qui y sont apparentées. Le virage qu'y prend l'auteur par rapport à son livre célèbre de 1979, Kant and the Claims of Taste, est également impressionnant. Moins dépendant des débats qui prédominaient dans l'esthétique de l'époque, il ne s'agit plus tant pour Guyer d'essayer de dégager le noyau nor
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
13

Cannon, Joseph. "The Moral Value of Artistic Beauty in Kant." Kantian Review 16, no. 1 (2011): 113–26. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1369415410000099.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
AbstractIn the third Critique, Kant argues that it is “always the mark of a good soul” to take an immediate interest in natural beauty, because it indicates an interest in harmony between nature and moral freedom. He, however, denies that there can be a similarly significant interest in artistic beauty. I argue that Kant ought not to deny this value to artistic beauty because his account of fine art as the joint product of the “natural gift” of genius and the discipline of taste commits him to the claim that artistic beauty expresses such a harmony between nature and freedom.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
14

Palmer, Linda. "A Universality Not Based on Concepts: Kant's Key to the Critique of Taste." Kantian Review 13, no. 1 (2008): 1–51. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1369415400001084.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
‘Beautiful is what, without a concept, is liked universally.’ Thus ends the second Moment of the Analytic of the Beautiful in Kant's Critique of Judgment.What could yield a non-conceptual universality? Kant finds this in the harmonious ‘free play’ of the mental powers, which he characterizes as a mental state that is both non-cognitive and inherently universally valid. In general, any interpretation of Kant's aesthetic theory will depend on the view of its relationship to cognition. This relationship itself should be understood in reference to Kant's notion of the mental state (or activity of
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
15

Hlobil, Tomáš. "Bolzanova revize Kantova pojetí Betrachtung ve sváru o předmět soudu vkusu." REFLEXE 2023, no. 64 (2023): 5–30. http://dx.doi.org/10.14712/25337637.2023.20.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
In German pre-critical aesthetics, the term Betrachtung (contemplation) was coined to describe the reception of beauty and art. It was also used by Immanuel Kant in his Critique of Judgment (1790), and by Bernard Bolzano in his treatise On the Concept of Beauty (1843). Both Bolzano and Kant tied the judgment of taste (beauty) to the mere contemplation of the initial object. However, each of them meant something different by this act, and each accorded it a different importance. The study describes Kant’s and Bolzano’s conceptions of mere contemplation, compares them and shows that Bolzano’s co
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
16

Day, Jonathan. "Jazz, Kant and Zen." Culture and Dialogue 4, no. 2 (2016): 301–16. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/24683949-12340017.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
Transgression and experimentation are at the heart of the musical composition with which this work begins. The compositional approaches employed developed from a consideration of Kant’s Critique of Judgement (1790) which offers a compelling explanation for the apparently bizarre “claim to objectivity” commonly made in judgements of taste. Kant’s final conclusion around the source of the claim is, for me, disappointing. This current work re-examines and extends his argument through an elision with Zen writing, and offers an alternate account. It is posited that the “claim to objectivity” operat
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
17

Corôa, Pedro Paulo Da Costa. "KANT, ROUSSEAU E AS BASES ESTÉTICAS DO PENSAMENTO." Cadernos de Pesquisa 22 (December 31, 2015): 66. http://dx.doi.org/10.18764/cp.v22i0.2974.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
O nosso objetivo é mostrar como a questão relativa ao gosto pode ser encontrada, enquanto forma particular de juízo, na obra de Rousseau, em especial, no Emílio. Em decorrência disso, tudo o que nós aprendemos sobre a gênese moderna do chamado juízo de reflexão estético, identificado à Crítica do juízo, de Kant, se não exige uma correção, nos obriga, pelo menos, a reconhecer, antes do esforço crítico, o surpreendente e certeiro tratamento do tema por parte de Rousseau. Palavras-chave: Rousseau. Kant. Gosto. Juízo. Reflexão. KANT, ROUSSEAU AND THE AESTHETIC BASIS OF THOUGHT Abstract: The aim of
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
18

Sánchez, Manuel. "The conclusion of the deduction of taste in the dialectic of the power of judgment aesthetic in Kant." Trans/Form/Ação 36, no. 2 (2013): 45–62. http://dx.doi.org/10.1590/s0101-31732013000200004.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
In this paper, it is argued that only in the section on dialectic in the Critique of Judgment does Kant reach a definitive and conclusive version of deduction, after discovering the concept of the supersensible. In the section on the deduction of pure aesthetic judgments, Kant does not satisfactorily explain the critical distinction between the sensible nature of humanity and the supersensible nature of human reason presupposed in the concept of universal communicability. While the concept of the supersensible illustrates this distinction, it is only through this concept that Kant that can jus
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
19

Rego, Pedro Costa. "Conhecimento e prazer na estética de Kant." Analytica - Revista de Filosofia 11, no. 2 (2013): 33–59. http://dx.doi.org/10.35920/arf.v11i2.530.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
O argumento de que Kant se serve para distinguir de saída, na Crítica da Faculdade do Juízo, o juízo de gosto do juízo de conhecimento teórico é o de que este último não é acompanhado de modo necessário por um sentimento de prazer, ao contrário do primeiro, que tem num sentimento de prazer sua razão determinante. Mas uma certa passagem da Introdução definitiva da obra parece infirmar essa posição clara da terceira Crítica, a de que onde há conhecimento (stricto sensu) não há geração necessária de sentimento de prazer, e de que se há prazer, então não estamos diante de um juízo de conhecimento
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
20

Corôa, Pedro Paulo Da Costa. "KANT, ROUSSEAU E AS BASES ESTÉTICAS DO PENSAMENTO." Cadernos de Pesquisa 22 (December 31, 2015): 66. http://dx.doi.org/10.18764/2178-2229/v.22n.especial/p.66-77.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
O nosso objetivo é mostrar como a questão relativa ao gosto pode ser encontrada, enquanto forma particular de juízo, na obra de Rousseau, em especial, no Emílio. Em decorrência disso, tudo o que nós aprendemos sobre a gênese moderna do chamado juízo de reflexão estético, identificado à Crítica do juízo, de Kant, se não exige uma correção, nos obriga, pelo menos, a reconhecer, antes do esforço crítico, o surpreendente e certeiro tratamento do tema por parte de Rousseau.Palavras-chave: Rousseau. Kant. Gosto. Juízo. Reflexão. KANT, ROUSSEAU AND THE AESTHETIC BASIS OF THOUGHT Abstract: The aim of
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
21

Draskic-Vicanovic, Iva. "Three directions of development of contemporary aesthetics." Theoria, Beograd 62, no. 2 (2019): 107–15. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/theo1902107d.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
The paper deals wit three possible directions of development which contemporary aesthetics can take. First: power of nation?s taste to show off the key characteristics of the whole culture and the spirit of epoche; author calls that ?logic of taste?. Second: development of combined application of phenomenological and iconological method in the analysis of the works of art in order to understand and interprete their context and third: possibility created by Fiedler?s aesthetic interpretation of Kant?s epistemology - development of the idea of formgiving, i.e. aesthetic, essence of human knowled
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
22

WANG, WEIJIA. "Beauty as the Symbol of Morality: A Twofold Duty in Kant’s Theory of Taste." Dialogue 57, no. 4 (2018): 853–75. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s001221731800015x.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
In the third Critique, Kant claims that beauty is the symbol of morality and that the consideration of this relation is a duty. This paper declares Kant’s argument to be twofold: firstly, experience of beauty strengthens our moral feeling. Secondly, in judging the beautiful, we assume some indeterminate purpose underlying nature, based on which we can conceive of nature as cooperative with our practical pursuit. Hence, for the sake of moral cultivation and moral motivation, it is our duty to regard beauty as the special symbol of morality.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
23

Krstic, Predrag. "Unwanted parenthood: Romanticism and Kant." Filozofija i drustvo 26, no. 1 (2015): 88–108. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/fid1501088k.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
Over the Romantic reception of Kant, the author attempts to show a relationship between the Romanticism and the Enlightenment. First part of the paper reconstructs the social conditions that created the strange path of transformation of parts of Kant?s teachings in the romantic motifs. The second part follows the theoretical precomposition of Kant?s thought in Fichte and expressly deviation from it in Novalis and Schlegel. Third section presents the key moments of the Romantic critique of the Enlightenment mind, and fourth its ambiguous pracital-political effects. In conclusion, it is suggeste
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
24

Baranzke, Heike. "Does Beast Suffering Count for Kant." Essays in Philosophy 5, no. 2 (2004): 375–90. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/eip2004529.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
Ever since Schopenhauer´s accusation, it has been disputed whether Kant´s few remarks concerning the ethical human-animal-relationship in the Lectures and in the Doctrine of Virtue fail to support ethical arguments on behalf of animals. One critique that plays a central role is whether Kant would have forbidden cruelty to brutes for educational purposes. In addition to these old objections, Kant´s ethics is charged to be speciesistic by animal ethicists and animal rights philosophers at present.The following article examines especially §17 of the Doctrine of Virtue, which is the only animal et
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
25

Soc, Andrija. "Kant and the legitimacy of rebellion against the sovereign." Theoria, Beograd 56, no. 4 (2013): 63–77. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/theo1304063s.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
The main topic of this paper is Kant?s position with respect to whether rebellion of citizens against their sovereign is justified. The first part of the paper introduces the social contract theory and considers three well-known answers to this question - Hobbes?s Locke?s and Rousseau?s. In the second part I deal with Kant?s views relying on those of his works where the relation between government and citizens is the chief subject. It is usually thought that Kant believes that rebellion, or revolution against sovereign is unjustified, or even contradictory. In the third part of the paper I try
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
26

Orlova, Yulia. "The concepts of apperception and reflection in Kant and the concept of reflection in Husserl." Studies in Transcendental Philosophy 4, no. 1 (2023): 0. http://dx.doi.org/10.18254/s271326680025802-2.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
The article considers reflection as a method and condition of the transcendental philosophy of Kant and Husserl. At the beginning, the author refers to Kant's predecessors who used the term reflection (Wolf, Baumgartner) and concludes that Kant, when referring to reflection, rather adheres to the tradition laid down by Leibniz. Based on the text of the “Critique of Pure Reason”, the article argues that it is with the help of reflection that the formation of a priori categories and a priori synthetic principles can be explained. The author distinguishes between reflection and the trans
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
27

Winegar, Reed. "Kant on God’s Intuitive Understanding: Interpreting CJ §76’s Modal Claims." Kantian Review 22, no. 2 (2017): 305–29. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1369415417000061.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
AbstractIn §76 of the third Critique, Kant claims that an intuitive understanding would represent no distinction between possible and actual things. Prior interpretations of §76 take Kant to claim that an intuitive understanding would produce things merely in virtue of thinking about them and, thus, could not think of merely possible things. In contrast, I argue that §76’s modal claims hinge on Kant’s suggestion that God represents things in their thoroughgoing determination, including in their connection to God’s actual will. I conclude by using my interpretation to argue that §76’s modal cla
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
28

Smajevic, Milica. "Deduction of morality and freedom in Kant’s ethics." Theoria, Beograd 63, no. 1 (2020): 29–42. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/theo2001029s.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
In the third section of the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant seeks, on the basis of the idea of the necessary presumption of freedom, to provide a deduction of the supreme moral principle and to prove its objective validity. Three years later, in the Critique of Practical Reason, he explicitly denies the possibility of making such deduction, and by changing methodological assumptions, tries to show that awareness of the moral law as a fact of reason is the basis for the deduction of freedom. In this paper we will argue that a direct contrast between Kant?s two texts clearly shows
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
29

CRISTY, RACHEL. "Does Wine Have a Place in Kant's Theory of Taste?" Journal of the American Philosophical Association 2, no. 1 (2016): 36–54. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/apa.2015.36.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
ABSTRACT:Kant claims in the third Critique that one can make about wine the merely subjective judgment that it is agreeable but never the universally valid judgment that it is beautiful. This follows from his views that judgments of beauty can be made only about the formal (spatiotemporal) features of a representation and that aromas and flavors consist of formless sensory matter. However, I argue that Kant's theory permits judgments of beauty about wine because the experience displays a temporal structure: the aromas and flavors evolve over the course of a tasting from the bouquet through the
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
30

Lazos, Efraín. "Kant y el conocimiento de sí mismo." Theoría. Revista del Colegio de Filosofía, no. 6 (November 1, 1998): 31–40. http://dx.doi.org/10.22201/ffyl.16656415p.1998.6.191.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
The paper takes up J. McDowell’s claim in Mind and World that the lack of a serious notion of second nature is an obstacle to an effective response by Kant to the Cartesian view of the self. A reconstruction of the Cartesian model of the mind is offered, as well as an analysis of key passages in the Critique of Pure Reason and P.F. Strawson ́s reception of them, to the effect that there is a sense in which Kant may successfully do away with Cartesian temptations without recourse to the abovementioned notion.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
31

Rosefeldt, Tobias. "Being Realistic about Kant’s Idealism (Translated by M. Rouba)." Studies in Transcendental Philosophy 2, no. 1 (2021): 0. http://dx.doi.org/10.18254/s271326680015447-1.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
This paper deals with the question of whether Kant's transcendental idealism allows for an explanation of the a posteriori aspects of mental content by the properties of empirical objects. I first show that a phenomenalist interpretation has severe problems with assuming that we perceive an object as being red or as being cubical partly because the perceived object is red and cubical, and then present an interpretation that allows us to save the realistic intuition behind these claims. According to this interpretation, Kantian phenomenal properties are understood as response-dependent
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
32

Govedarica, Jelena. "Kant’s conception of enlightenment." Theoria, Beograd 64, no. 2 (2021): 49–67. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/theo2102049g.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
By interpreting the basic concepts of Kant?s definition of enlightenment, as well as pointing out the importance of discussion for the development of understanding and explaining the role of state power in educating citizens, the author argues that enlightenment ought to be understood as an imperfect duty of every human being. This duty belongs to the duty of virtue according to which we are obligated, among other things, to advance our own perfection. In order to better understand the responsibility for one?s own minority and meaning of the independent use of one?s own understanding, she expl
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
33

Merritt, Melissa McBay. "Analysis in the Critique of Pure Reason." Kantian Review 12, no. 1 (2007): 61–89. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1369415400000819.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
It is widely supposed that the principal task of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason is to carry out some kind of analysis of experience. Commentators as profoundly at odds on fundamental points of interpretation as P. F. Strawson and Patricia Kitcher share this supposition. In a letter to J. S. Beck, Kant seems to endorse this view himself, referring to some unspecified stretch of the Critique as an ‘analysis of experience in general’. The idea that the Critique is engaged in an analysis of experience accords well with an attractive conception of Critical philosophy as making something explicit th
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
34

Fedorchenko, Yurii. "Experience of the Preface to Immanuel Kant`s Critique of Pure Reason Translation." Filosofiya osvity. Philosophy of Education 28, no. 1 (2022): 212–21. http://dx.doi.org/10.31874/2309-1606-2022-28-1-13.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
The article provides a substantive philosophical, philological and translation­al analysis of each paragraph of the Preface to Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. It is revealed the conceptual character of the Preface’s formulations, which shows the logic of the movement of Kant’s thought in philosophy. In particular, the complexity of the problems of Kant’s philosophical research and the unity of his phil­osophical position, which can be traced in various works of Kant, are visualized. In this light, the Preface acts both as a certain summary and as a general direction for Kant’s subsequ
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
35

Jiang, Qirui. "Kantian Aesthetics: Free Beauty in Fine Arts." BCP Social Sciences & Humanities 15 (March 13, 2022): 121–31. http://dx.doi.org/10.54691/bcpssh.v15i.371.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
A rose is beautiful. The Mona Lisa is beautiful. What is the difference between these two objects in being beautiful? In Critique of Judgment, Kant famously answers this question with a demarcation between two kinds of beauty: free beauty (pulchritudo vaga) and adherent beauty (pulchritudo adhaerens). Natural objects, e.g., a rose, fall into the realm of free beauty while works of fine arts, e.g., the Mona Lisa, adherent beauty. Objects of free beauty do not presuppose conceptual understanding while that of adherent beauty do. We do not regard some objective rules, if any, for the beauty of a
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
36

Dejeanne, Solange. "Felicidade e dignidade de ser feliz: o sumo bem como ideal dialético da razão prática pura." Studia Kantiana 9, no. 11 (2011): 56. http://dx.doi.org/10.5380/sk.v9i11.88770.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
Na análise (no seu Commentary on Kant"s Critique of Practical Reason) da questão se existe uma necessidade moral de promover o sumo bem, L.W. Beck considera que Kant engana-se ao defender a possibilidade de uma conexão a priori, necessária, entre virtude e felicidade, e simplesmente observa que nem na natureza nem na lei moral Kant pode encontrar algo mais do que uma conexão contingente entre virtude e felicidade. E assim ele apresenta sua tese em relação ao conceito de sumo bem: não constitui um conceito prático, mas um ideal dialético da razão. - à luz da interpretação de Beck e, principalme
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
37

Moledo, Fernando. "Kants teleologische Überlegungen zur Menschenwürde in der Vorlesung über Naturrecht Feyerabend." Studia Kantiana 19, no. 1 (2023): 31. http://dx.doi.org/10.5380/sk.v19i1.90216.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
In this paper I deal with an argument for the foundation of human dignity that Kant sketches in the introduction to his lecture Feyerabend on natural law (1784). After presenting very briefly Kant's discussion of Achenwall's concept of value I argue that the starting point of the argument on human dignity that Kant develops in the introduction to the lecture is teleological. I discuss then the problems that such a starting point inevitably entails regarding Kant´s practical philosophy and offer an explanation as to why Kant was able to include this argument in the introduction to his lecture d
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
38

Romcevic, Branko. "Foucault’s critical ontology." Theoria, Beograd 66, no. 4 (2023): 111–32. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/theo2304111r.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
In this paper, we deal with Foucault?s interpretation of Kant?s understanding of Aufkl?rung and critique, following first reactions to his later interest in these topics. Then we present the textual situation through which Foucault?s attitude towards Kant was determined, starting with his supplementary thesis from 1961, through the ninth chapter of Order of Things (1966), and up to the text ?What is Enlightenment?? from 1984. In addition, we find that the central was his lecture given in 1978, which was published in 1990. In contains several motifs from Order of Things (related to the question
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
39

최재석. "A Study on the 'Color' Concept in I. Kant`s Critique of Judgment." Journal of Korea Society of Color Studies 24, no. 2 (2010): 67–78. http://dx.doi.org/10.17289/jkscs.24.2.201005.67.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
40

Ahn, Hyun-seok. "The Moral Interpretation and Critique in Kant`s Idea of the Highest Good." Journal of Gamsung 13 (September 29, 2016): 61–92. http://dx.doi.org/10.37996/jog.13.3.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
41

Prole, Dragan. "Kant and the romantic ontology." Filozofija i drustvo 26, no. 1 (2015): 47–68. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/fid1501047p.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
In the first part of the paper, the author displays the specificities of the romantic concept of subjectivity. Based on the assumption that the Man is but a minute part of what he might be, the romantics emphasize on the imperative of infinite subjectivity. Giving up on the division of philosophical disciplines, the romantics request a unity of spirit in history. The relationship between Kant and romanticism is mostly deliberated under the auspices of the terms of anarchy and the nomadic spirit, which are pointed out by Kant in the beginning of the foreword to the first edition of the Critique
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
42

Nikolic, Olga, and Igor Cvejic. "Social justice and the formal principle of freedom." Filozofija i drustvo 28, no. 2 (2017): 270–84. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/fid1702270n.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
The aim of this paper is to show, contra the right-libertarian critique of social justice, that there are good reasons for defending policies of social justice within a free society. In the first part of the paper, we will present two influential right-libertarian critiques of social justice, found in Friedrich Hayek?s Law, Legislation and Liberty and Robert Nozick?s Anarchy, State and Utopia. Based on their approach, policies of social justice are seen as an unjustified infringement on freedoms of individual members of a society. In response to this critique, we will introduce the distincion
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
43

Dimic, Zoran. "On artistic shaping of citizens’ political gatherings." Filozofija i drustvo 24, no. 3 (2013): 23–33. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/fid1303023d.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
Following the new reading of Kant?s third critique, which was proposed by Hannah Arendt in her Lectures on Kant?s Political Philosophy, in this paper, the author deals with the function of art in the establishment, organization and profiling of political communities. The focus is primarily on the field of music. The analysis begins with ancient philosophers (Pythagoras, Plato, Aristotle) and continues with the problems which relate to artistic shaping of citizens? lives in modern epoch (Rousseau, Kant, Schiller). The goal of the paper is to show that the philosophy of art and the philosophy of
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
44

Omar Perez, Daniel. "Ontology, metaphysics and criticism as Transcendental Semantics as of Kant." Revista de Filosofia Aurora 28, no. 44 (2016): 459. http://dx.doi.org/10.7213/aurora.28.044.ds04.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
The aim of this paper is to present the core of Kant´s critique of traditional metaphysics and ontology as a transcendental semantics that allows reformulating the problem about the objects and their reality. In order to achieve this purpose, we propound a paper divided in two parts: 1. A brief justification of Kant’s semantics interpretation; 2. A work program based on a semantics comprehended as a fundamental part of a method of resolution of philosophical problems. Basically, we can state that the critical position against traditional metaphysics and ontology leads to the question upon: how
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
45

Kononetc, Daria. "Question about the World and Eugen Fink`s Cosmological Interpretation of Kant`s “Critique of Pure Reason”." HORIZON. Studies in Phenomenology 4, no. 1 (2015): 224–39. http://dx.doi.org/10.18199/2226-5260-2015-4-1-224-239.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
46

Yi, Gyeong-hee. "The Way to Morality in Kant`s Aesthetics - Four Concepts in Critique of Jedgement." Journal of Gamsung 14 (March 30, 2017): 183–218. http://dx.doi.org/10.37996/jog.14.6.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
47

Hrnjez, Sasa. "Cancellation of time: On two modes of extemporalization in Kant and Hegel." Filozofija i drustvo 26, no. 3 (2015): 730–52. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/fid1503730h.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
This article examines two modes of the canceling of time in a comparative analysis that ought to show the passage from the aesthetic over coming of the form of time in Kant to the historical over coming of natural time in Hegel. The essay begins with a problematization of the form of time in Kant?s first Critique and with the question whet her Kant displaces time outside the framework of mere condition of receptivity. Thereafter we will analyze the key passage from Analytics of the Sublime where Kant writes about the cancellation of time-condition and we will interpret this in the light of an
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
48

Baggett, David. "Might Beauty Bolster the Moral Argument for God?" Religions 14, no. 8 (2023): 1029. http://dx.doi.org/10.3390/rel14081029.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
John Hare argues that Kant, in his Third Critique, offers an aesthetic argument for God’s existence that shares premises with his famous moral argument. Karl Ameriks demurs, expressing skepticism that this is so. In this paper, I stake out an intermediate position, arguing that the resources of Kant provide ingredients for an aesthetic argument, but one distinctly less than a transcendental argument for God or an entailment relation. Whether the argument is best thought of as abductive in nature, a C-inductive argument, or a Pascalian natural sign, prospects for its formulation are strong. And
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
49

Filho, Edgard José Jorge. "SOBRE O LIVRE JOGO DA IMAGINAÇÃO COM O ENTENDIMENTO NO JUÍZO DE GOSTO, EM KANT." Síntese: Revista de Filosofia 35, no. 112 (2010): 221. http://dx.doi.org/10.20911/21769389v35n112p221-237/2008.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
Na Crítica da Faculdade do Juízo, Kant põe como fundamento do juízo de gosto o livre jogo da imaginação com o entendimento, que, ao produzir o acordo da liberdade da imaginação com a legalidade do entendimento, engendra o prazer sobre o qual se funda esse juízo. O objetivo deste estudo é procurar esclarecer em que consiste a liberdade desse jogo e acordo, considerando, inicialmente, que o princípio da faculdade de juízo reflexiva tem a forma do dever e que, portanto, a imaginação e o entendimento, atuantes nessa faculdade, estariam submetidos a deveres incondicionais, podendo-se atribuir-lhes
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
50

Kormin, Nikolai Aleksandrovich. "I. Kant: perfection within the structure of the aesthetic field of metaphysics." Философия и культура, no. 3 (March 2021): 22–55. http://dx.doi.org/10.7256/2454-0757.2021.3.35612.

Der volle Inhalt der Quelle
Annotation:
The subject of this research is the interrelation between aesthetics and metaphysics as it is reflected in the Kantian transcendentalism. In the “Critique of Judgment”, Kant assumes that the representation of perfection does not correlate with such on the sense of delight; thus, in the first introduction to the “Critique of Judgment”, he is far from considering the solutions to the problem of interrelation between perfection and aesthetic sense of delight persuasive. However, the attitude towards perfection transforms in Kant's later works, the analysis
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO und andere Zitierweisen
Wir bieten Rabatte auf alle Premium-Pläne für Autoren, deren Werke in thematische Literatursammlungen aufgenommen wurden. Kontaktieren Sie uns, um einen einzigartigen Promo-Code zu erhalten!