Inhaltsverzeichnis
Auswahl der wissenschaftlichen Literatur zum Thema „Histoire des idées pénales“
Geben Sie eine Quelle nach APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard und anderen Zitierweisen an
Machen Sie sich mit den Listen der aktuellen Artikel, Bücher, Dissertationen, Berichten und anderer wissenschaftlichen Quellen zum Thema "Histoire des idées pénales" bekannt.
Neben jedem Werk im Literaturverzeichnis ist die Option "Zur Bibliographie hinzufügen" verfügbar. Nutzen Sie sie, wird Ihre bibliographische Angabe des gewählten Werkes nach der nötigen Zitierweise (APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver usw.) automatisch gestaltet.
Sie können auch den vollen Text der wissenschaftlichen Publikation im PDF-Format herunterladen und eine Online-Annotation der Arbeit lesen, wenn die relevanten Parameter in den Metadaten verfügbar sind.
Zeitschriftenartikel zum Thema "Histoire des idées pénales"
Normandeau, André. „Histoire des doctrines pénales“. Canadian Journal of Criminology 34, Nr. 1 (Januar 1992): 97–100. http://dx.doi.org/10.3138/cjcrim.34.1.97.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleBourgeois, Isabelle. „Histoire des idées“. Regards sur l’économie allemande, Nr. 118-119 (31.12.2015): 46. http://dx.doi.org/10.4000/rea.4927.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleMargolin, Jean-Claude, Denis McKee, Michèle et Karl Aderhold, Joël Cornette, John Pappas und Catherine Chevalley. „Histoire des Idées“. Revue de synthèse 108, Nr. 2 (April 1987): 323–40. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/bf03189062.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleHesse, Carla. „La logique culturelle de la loi révolutionnaire“. Annales. Histoire, Sciences Sociales 57, Nr. 4 (August 2002): 915–33. http://dx.doi.org/10.3406/ahess.2002.280086.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleHerschberg-Pierrot, Anne. „Histoire d'« idées reçues »“. Romantisme 24, Nr. 86 (1994): 101–20. http://dx.doi.org/10.3406/roman.1994.5990.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleRoche, Daniel. „Histoire des idées, histoire sociale : l'exemple français“. Revue d’histoire moderne et contemporaine 59-4bis, Nr. 5 (2012): 9. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/rhmc.595.0009.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleLécrivain, Philippe. „Histoire des idées médiévales (1)“. Recherches de Science Religieuse 94, Nr. 3 (2006): 473. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/rsr.063.0473.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleLécrivain, Philippe. „Histoire des idées médiévales (2)“. Recherches de Science Religieuse 94, Nr. 4 (2006): 625. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/rsr.064.0625.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleBreaugh, Martin. „La démocratie : histoire des idées.“ Canadian Journal of Political Science 39, Nr. 3 (September 2006): 728–30. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0008423906419971.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleLamonde, Yvan. „Le politique en histoire des idées“. Bulletin d'histoire politique 18, Nr. 3 (2010): 137. http://dx.doi.org/10.7202/1054832ar.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleDissertationen zum Thema "Histoire des idées pénales"
Frambéry-Iacobone, Alexandre. „La recherche de l'intention en droit pénal contemporain (XIXe-XXe siècles)“. Electronic Thesis or Diss., Bordeaux, 2022. http://www.theses.fr/2022BORD0446.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleThe understanding of intention may seem excessively simple, as may its definition. We could say that intention is what we want, in our innermost being, without necessarily waiting for an externalisation. In this hypothesis, the intention is eminently personal, but also immaterial since it has no anchorage in the sensible world at this stage. In the same way, we could consider that intentional action would correspond to a determined act, caused with a determined will. Here, the action comes out of the inner world to enter the outer world. The entry into the tangible world is, moreover, a condition for the law to begin to take an interest in intentions, whereas religion, for example, can be satisfied with impure thoughts to act. However, once we have laid down these elements, if we want to scrape off this pragmatic veneer, the situation becomes more difficult: in short, we have said everything and nothing at the same time. Indeed, what is the will? How can we prove intention? Can we think of criminal law without intentionality? These are some of the questions that may arise, especially in a legalistic system. However delicate it may be to grasp, intention has nevertheless found its way into our criminal legislation. Given the absence of an operative definition, whether legislative, jurisprudential, or doctrinal, it may therefore seem interesting to adopt a historical approach to try to understand and master the ideological underpinnings that may have worked to impose such a notion. In addition, concrete work on the way in which the justice system can deal with the intentional question must be carried out, by mobilising archival sources, interviews with justice professionals, or by analysing doctrinal statements on the subject, among other things. Finally, it is once we try to understand, concretely, what intention can be, that we note its eminently fleeting, almost evanescent status, and that we can question the compatibility of the notion with the concomitant construction of a criminal law subject to certain cardinal principles, such as the principle of criminal legality
Labbé, Éric. „Polémique sur le droit de grâce, 1789-1791 : fondements éthiques et politiques“. Thesis, Université Laval, 2008. http://www.theses.ulaval.ca/2008/25116/25116.pdf.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleGuigui, Julien. „La loi pénale et les titulaires des fonctions publiques : essai critique sur la dénaturation polémique des débats entourant l'application du droit pénal aux agents publics et élus“. Cergy-Pontoise, 2009. http://biblioweb.u-cergy.fr/theses/09CERG0407.pdf.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleThe continuous acceleration of technical progress and the criminalisation of social relations were two of the most characteristic features of the last century. This evolution did not spare the domain of administrative proceedings. Nevertheless, the difficulties linked to the application of criminal law to civil servants and elected representatives only really come into play in the assumption that the substance of the moral element likely to serve as a medium for criminal sanctions is weak. Such criminalisation of behaviour which is sometimes based more on simple maladministration than on anti-social dealings is fraught with consequences. For holders of public office, it leads especially to the appearance of self-defence strategies which often result in a retreat of public services as well as that of local democracy. The legislator has tried to offset these deviations on two occasions. But the movement of criminalisation of public proceedings, at its most excessive, is accompanied and encouraged by part of legal doctrine, especially criminal doctrine. The latter, by vigorously professing the idea according to which respect for the principle of equality left no other choice to national representation than that of adopting laws of general application, weighed considerably on debate surrounding the adoption of the laws of 13 May 1996 and of 10 July 2000. The effectiveness of these measures suffered considerably as a result of this fact. The views of advocates of that which Professor Olivier BEAUD calls “the ideology of common law” are hinged mainly on three erroneous axioms: a questionable definition of equality before criminal law, negation of the unique nature of missions carried out by holders of public office and the affirmation of substitutability of criminal liability with political responsibility. All three have led to the serious controversial denaturing of discussions in relation to these difficult issues. This thesis tries to seek the causes of this denaturing by carrying out a systematic exploration of the evolution of criminal law applicable to holders of public office from the Ancien Régime until today (Part One). This historic study of the evolution of substantive law and the legal doctrines associated, provide several clues allowing us in particular to understand the origin of the notion of substitutability of criminal liability with political responsibility or even to explain why the problems linked to criminal prosecution of involuntary offences have only appeared relatively recently. It especially brings to light the influence of the memory of the system of prior authorisation to prosecute on current-day debate. The study of substantive criminal law (Part Two) highlights the fact that concerning voluntary offences, holders of public office have always been the subject of specific accusations aimed at protecting the correct operation of the public services of which they are in charge. They therefore indisputably make up a distinct category of recipients of criminal law to which special rules apply. Such an observation radically contradicts the dominating doctrinal positions from 1996 and 2000. It suggests that it would not only be possible but also crucial to adapt criminal prosecution of involuntary offences to the specificities of the situation of holders of public office. Such is the position defended in this thesis. For the lack of having been definitively settled by the law of 10 July 2000, the issue of the application of criminal law to civil servants and elected representatives will necessarily be raised again before the national representation in the years to come. By contributing to exorcising the old demons of Article 75 of the French Constitution of the Year VIII, we hope that this critical essay will contribute to the fact that this Constitution is debated more serenely and on an exact scientific basis
Stoll, Claude. „Histoire des idées sur l'évolution de l'homme“. Université Louis Pasteur (Strasbourg) (1971-2008), 2008. https://publication-theses.unistra.fr/public/theses_doctorat/2008/STOLL_Claude_2008_1.pdf.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleSUMMARY : Until the 18th century theologians and philosophers were debating on human origin. According to Genesis, the Earth was 6000 years old. Around 1866, Buffon thought that the Earth is older, 3 millions years and that species are issued from common ancestors. In 1809 Lamarck proposed that creation of the most common beings is persistent and their transformation progressive, adaptation to external environment being responsible for their diversity. In 1833, Etienne Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire considered that there are relationships between the extinct and the present species. In 1859 Darwin published The Origin of Species proposing a theory of evolution based on variation and selection. However, Wallace proposed the same theory before him, in 1855. In 1874, Haeckel postulated that man originated during the Eocene, for him the Pithecanthrope is the missing link between the great apes and man. In 1902, the mutationism was a major step in the understanding of the mechanisms of speciation. Between 1930 and 1950 the request of a consensus resulted in the Modern Synthethis which was completed, around 1970 by the neutral theory of molecular evolution and by evo-devo. According to the fossil record the origin of man is disputed. Among the numerous scenarios proposed since 1980, the most common is the one suggesting that our ancestor went out of Africa some 2 millions years ago. The results of the karyotype and the molecular biology showed that there are very few differences between the genomes of man and of chimpanzee. Recently, efforts were done to come out with a consensus. If genetic studies suggest that man and chimpanzee are sister species, they showed a paradox: there is a gap between the history of genes, their divergence and the history of species, the speciation. Many scenarios of hominisation were proposed
Andioc, Torres Sophie. „Les idées politiques et littéraires de Domingo Del Monte“. Paris 8, 1993. http://www.theses.fr/1993PA080713.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleDomingo del monte was a central figure of the cuban society of the xix th century. He spent his life taking part in the marking events of the histoire of the colony from 1803 to 1853. He was the subject for every cultural polemics and for every political stir stemming from the conflicts between the romanticists and the neo-classicists, between the partisans of prioslavery and the abolitionists and between the reformists and the annexionists. His stances not only emerged from his actions in the society of his time. He also left us a written account in wich he proposes a wide and very complete programme meant to assure definitively the prosperity of cuba. In litterature, he recommended a raising of moral standards in plotsand language, as well as the creation of a peculiar litterature schowing the cultural originality of the island. He conceived a plan of reform for education in order to spread primary instruction to the whole population. In politic he claimed a larger autonomy compatible with the loyalty of the colony with spain. So he marked the history of ideas by his patriotism and his conception of the citizen utility
Wegener, Kim. „Le vécu de réalités fictives : histoire des idées et psychopathologie“. Brest, 1997. http://www.theses.fr/1997BRES1008.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleFoisy-Geoffroy, Dominique. „Les idées politiques des intellectuels traditionalistes canadiens-français 1940-1960“. Thesis, Université Laval, 2008. http://www.theses.ulaval.ca/2008/25480/25480.pdf.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleBlanc, François-Pierre. „L'adultère en droit pénal français : histoire juridique et politique d'une infraction : 1803-1975“. Perpignan, 2003. http://www.theses.fr/2003PERP0495.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleAdultery has figured in various forms in the repressive arsenal of successive legislators who, from the 1789 revolution to the current day, have studied fidelity between spouses ; with the current disapperance of adultery as penal offence, the judical evolution of marriage shows the protection which, following successive acquisitions of new-found freedom and equality (sexual freedom, equality of the sexes, has become of less and less concern to law order. The history of adultery as a penal offence, is thus indissociable from the evolution of a socio-religious concept : the indissolubility of marriage. When associated the indissolubility of marriage, this incrimination tends to censure the finality, which is notably to enable christian spouses to remain as one at the centre of the united family. The penal offence thus ensures the defence of marriage, a fundamental social institution. The incrimination on the other hand, tends to disappear during periods of dissolubility of marriage, when it loses its consistence, to leave the institutional field for simple contractual field ; in this case adultery is simply a civil incident. Two important period mark recent history of adultery as a penal offence. From 1816 to 1884 it was the main rampart af the indissoluble marriage (Part I) ; from 1884, the offence, henceforthat the service of dissoluble marriage, lost any reason to exist and became ineffective before completely disappearing (Part II)
Martin-Condé, Francette. „Les idées gnostiques chez Flaubert“. Nancy 2, 1990. http://www.theses.fr/1990NAN21017.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleBeyond its historical character, Gnosticism is also an existential attitude; Gnostics ideas may reappear spontaneously through ages without being brought by a direct tradition. After a search which makes emerge, in Flaubert’s works, expressions, themes and a structure very much like Gnostics ones, it seems that we could as a work-hypothesis-inscribe Flaubert on the list of "instinctive Gnostics" who rose since early Gnosticism disappeared
Petges, Sophie. „Dermatomyosite : naissance d'un concept et évolution des idées dans l'école bordelaise“. Bordeaux 2, 1992. http://www.theses.fr/1992BOR2M031.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleBücher zum Thema "Histoire des idées pénales"
Pradel, Jean. Histoire des doctrines pénales. Paris: Presses universitaires de France, 1989.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle findenPradel, Jean. Histoire des doctrines pénales. Paris: Presses universitaires de France, 1989.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle findenHistoire des idées. Paris: Ellipses, 2013.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle findenNay, Olivier. Histoire des idées politiques. Paris: Armand Colin, 2004.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle findenGuchet, Yves. Histoire des idées politiques. Paris: A. Colin, 1995.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle findenPisier-Kouchner, Evelyne. Histoire des idées politiques. Paris: Quadrige/PUF, 2004.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle findenEvelyne, Pisier, Hrsg. Histoire des idées politique. 4. Aufl. Paris: Presses universitaires de France, 1996.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle findenTouchard, Jean. Histoire des idées politiques. Paris: Presses universitaires de France, 1988.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle findenLescuyer, Georges. Histoire des idées politiques. Paris: Dalloz, 2001.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle findenChâtelet, François. Histoire des idées politiques. 2. Aufl. Paris: Presses universitaires de France, 1989.
Den vollen Inhalt der Quelle findenBuchteile zum Thema "Histoire des idées pénales"
Angenot, Marc. „Histoire des idées et histoire rhétorique et cognitive“. In Histoire et historiens des idées, 39–51. Collège de France, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.4000/books.cdf.9868.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleNay, Olivier. „Chapitre 4. De la Renaissance aux Lumières : l’individu, la raison et la liberté“. In Histoire des idées politiques, 217–58. Armand Colin, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/arco.nayco.2016.01.0217.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleNay, Olivier. „Chapitre 8. La question démocratique au tournant du XXIe siècle“. In Histoire des idées politiques, 555–617. Armand Colin, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/arco.nayco.2016.01.0555.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleNay, Olivier. „Chapitre 6. La société industrielle en question : utopies sociales, socialismes et pensée révolutionnaire“. In Histoire des idées politiques, 377–496. Armand Colin, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/arco.nayco.2016.01.0377.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleNay, Olivier. „Chapitre 7. Les sentinelles de la liberté : critiques du totalitarisme, éloge de la société libérale“. In Histoire des idées politiques, 497–554. Armand Colin, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/arco.nayco.2016.01.0497.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleNay, Olivier. „Chapitre 1. L’invention de la raison politique dans le monde antique“. In Histoire des idées politiques, 9–68. Armand Colin, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/arco.nayco.2016.01.0009.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleNay, Olivier. „Chapitre 3. Les doctrines de l’État : des théories absolutistes au modèle de la monarchie limitée“. In Histoire des idées politiques, 137–216. Armand Colin, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/arco.nayco.2016.01.0137.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleNay, Olivier. „Chapitre 5. La Révolution française et ses prolongements : du peuple souverain au gouvernement représentatif“. In Histoire des idées politiques, 259–376. Armand Colin, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/arco.nayco.2016.01.0259.
Der volle Inhalt der QuelleNay, Olivier. „Chapitre 2. La pensée politique au Moyen Âge : de l’ordre chrétien à la « renaissance » philosophique“. In Histoire des idées politiques, 69–136. Armand Colin, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/arco.nayco.2016.01.0069.
Der volle Inhalt der Quelle„Bibliographie“. In Histoire des idées économiques, 295–98. Armand Colin, 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/arco.coeur.2017.02.0295.
Der volle Inhalt der Quelle